Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-q6k6v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-10T19:21:42.456Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

1 - Introduction: Becoming Paul M. Churchland (1942–)

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

Brian L. Keeley
Affiliation:
Pitzer College in Claremont
Brian L. Keeley
Affiliation:
Pitzer College, Claremont
Get access

Summary

The goal of this chapter is two-fold. First, I will present an overview of the philosophical vision of Paul M. Churchland (PMC). This will help situate the more detailed, and necessarily narrower, discussions of the other authors in this volume. Second, the more substantive goal here is to show that Paul Churchland's views have not developed in a vacuum. While he has clearly developed his own unique view of the philosophical terrain, he is not without his influences – influences that he in no way attempts to hide. His work is a unique blend of ideas encountered as a nascent philosopher. The philosophers I will be discussing are not always so well known to today's students of philosophy, so there is value in considering how these views of the preceding generation are being passed on within the work of one of today's more influential philosophers of mind and science.

I will begin by sketching Paul Churchland's personal biography. After getting the basic facts on the table, I will turn to the three philosophers whose influence on PMC are my foci: Russell Hanson, Wilfrid Sellars, and Paul Feyerabend. Each of these thinkers made philosophical contributions that are reflected in the work of PMC. Next, I will show how all three of these thinkers contributed to the philosophical position most closely associated with Churchland, namely “Eliminative Materialism.”

Type
Chapter
Information
Paul Churchland , pp. 1 - 31
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Batterman, R. W. (2001). The devil in the details: Asymptotic reasoning in explanation, reduction and emergence. Oxford, Oxford University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bickle, J. (1998). Psychoneural reduction: The new wave. Cambridge, MA, MIT Press (A Bradford Book)Google Scholar
Bickle, J.. (2003). Philosophy and neuroscience: A ruthlessly reductive account. Dordrecht, The Netherlands, Kluwer Academic PublishersCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boghossian, P. (1990). “The status of content.” The Philosophical Review 99: 157–84CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. M. (1979). Scientific realism and the plasticity of mind. New York, Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. M.. (1981/1989). “Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes.” The Journal of Philosophy78(2): 67–90. Reprinted as Chapter 1 of Paul M. Churchland, A neurocomputational perspective: The nature of mind and structure of science. Cambridge, MA, The MIT Press (A Bradford Book), 1989Google Scholar
Churchland, P. M.. (1989). A neurocomputational perspective: The nature of mind and the structure of science. Cambridge, MA, The MIT Press (A Bradford Book)Google Scholar
Churchland, P. M.. (1995). The engine of reason, the seat of the soul: A philosophical journey into the brain. Cambridge, MA, The MIT Press (A Bradford Book)Google Scholar
Churchland, P. M.. (1998). “Conceptual similarity across sensory and neural diversity: The FodorLepore challenge answered.” The Journal of Philosophy 95: 5–32Google Scholar
Churchland, P. M. (2002). “Catching consciousness in a recurrent net.” Daniel Dennett. Brook, A. and Ross, D. (Eds.) New York, Cambridge University Press, 64–81Google Scholar
ChurchlandChurchland, P. M. P. S. (1998). On the contrary: Critical essays,1987–1997. Cambridge, MA, The MIT Press (A Bradford Book)Google Scholar
Churchland, P. M., and Hooker, C. A., Eds. (1985). Images of science: Essays on realism and empiricism, with a reply from Bas C. Van Fraassen. Chicago, The University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. S. (1986a). Neurophilosophy: Toward a unified science of the mindbrain. Cambridge, MA, The MIT Press (A Bradford Book)Google Scholar
Churchland, P. S.. (1986b). “Replies to comments.” Inquiry29: 241–72CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clark, A. (1989). Microcognition: Philosophy, cognitive science, and parallel distributed processing. Cambridge, MA, The MIT Press (A Bradford Book)Google Scholar
Dennett, D. C. (1986). “The logical geography of computational approaches: A view from the east pole.” The representation of knowledge and belief. M. Brand and M. Harnish (Eds.) Tucson, University of Arizona Press: 59–79. Reprinted as Daniel C. Dennett, Brainchildren: Essays on designing minds. Cambridge, MA, The MIT Press (A Bradford Book), 1998, 215–34Google Scholar
Vries, W. A., and T. Triplett (2000). Knowledge, mind, and the given: Reading Wilfrid Sellars's “empiricism and the philosophy of the mind.” Indianapolis, Hackett Publishing Company, IncGoogle Scholar
Duhem, P. (1914). La théorie physique. Paris, M. Rivière.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, P. K. (1962). “Explanation, reduction and empiricism.” Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science: Scientific explanation, space and time. Feigl, H. and Maxwell, G. (Eds.) Minneapolis. Volume 3: 28–97Google Scholar
Feyerabend, P. K.. (1963a). “Materialism and the mind-body problem.” Review of Metaphysics 17: 49–66Google Scholar
Feyerabend, P. K.. (1963b). “Mental events and the brain.” The Journal of Philosophy ⅬX: 11Google Scholar
Feyerabend, P. K. (1975). “How to defend society against science.” Radical Philosophy11: 3–8. Reprinted in Introductory readings in the philosophy of science, revised edition. Klemke, E. D., Hollinger, Robert, & Kline, David A.. (Eds.). Buffalo, NY, Prometheus Books, 1998, 54–65Google Scholar
Feyerabend, P. K.. (1995). Killing time: The autobiography of Paul Feyerabend. Chicago, University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. A. (1975). The language of thought. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University PressGoogle Scholar
Hanson, N. R. (1958). Patterns of discovery: An inquiry into the conceptual foundations of science. Cambridge, UK, Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Hanson, N. R.. (1963). The concept of the positron: A philosophical analysis. New York, Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Hanson, N. R.. (1971). Observation and explanation: A guide to philosophy of science. New York, Harper TorchbooksGoogle Scholar
Hooker, C. A. (1975). “The philosophical ramifications of the information-processing approach to the brain-mind.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 36: 1–15CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hooker, C. A.. (1981a). “Towards a general theory of reductionism, part i: Historical framework.” Dialogue 20: 38–59CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hooker, C. A.. (1981b). “Towards a general theory of reductionism, part ii: Identity and reduction.” Dialogue 20: 201–36CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hooker, C. A.. (1981c). “Towards a general theory of reductionism, part iii: Cross-categorial reduction.” Dialogue 20: 496–529CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kekulé, F. A. (1890/1996). Origin of benzene and structural theory. Introduction to the philosophy of science. Zucker, A. (Ed.) Upper Saddle River, NJ, Prentice Hall, 34–5Google Scholar
Laakso, A., and Cottrell, G. W. (1998). “How can I know what you think?: Assessing representational similarity in neural systems.” Proceedings of the twentieth annual cognitive science conference, Madison, Wi.Mahwah, NJ, Lawrence ErlbaumGoogle Scholar
Laakso, A., and Cottrell, G. W.. (2000). “Content and cluster analysis: Assessing representational similarity in neural systems.” Philosophical Psychology 13: 47–76CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakatos, I., and Musgrave, A., Eds. (1970). Criticism and the growth of knowledge. Cambridge, UK, Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, C. I. (1929). Mind and the world-order. New York, Charles Scribner's SonsGoogle Scholar
Lewis, C. I.. (1945). An analysis of knowledge and valuation. La Salle, IL, The Open Court Publishing CompanyGoogle Scholar
McClelland, J. L., and Rumelhart, D. E. (1986). Parallel distributed processing: Explorations in the microstructures of cognition. Cambridge, MA, The MIT Press (A Bradford Book)Google Scholar
Place, U. T. (1956). “Is consciousness a brain process?” The British Journal of Psychology47: 44–50. Reprinted in Identifying the Mind: Selected Papers of U.T. Place. U. T. Place, Elizabeth R. Valentine, George Graham. Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2003, 45–52Google Scholar
Preston, J. (2000). Feyerabend. A companion to the philosophy of science. W. H. Newton-Smith (Ed.) Malden, MA, Blackwell Publishers, 143–8Google Scholar
Prinz, J. J. (2002). Furnishing the mind: Concepts and their perceptual basis. Cambridge, MA, The MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. (1959). “Review of Norwood Russell Hanson, Patterns of discovery. An inquiry into the conceptual foundations of science.” Science 129(3364): 1666–7Google Scholar
Putnam, H.. (1963). “Review of Norwood Russell Hanson, The concept of the positron: A philosophical analysis.” Science 139(3556): 745CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rorty, R. (1997). “Introduction.” Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. W. Sellars (Ed.) Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 1–12Google Scholar
Rumelhart, D. E., and McClelland, J. L. (1986). Parallel distributed processing: Explorations in the microstructures of cognition. Cambridge, MA, The MIT Press (A Bradford Book)Google Scholar
Sellars, W. (1956/1997). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 1: The Foundations of Science and the Concepts of Psychology and Psychoanalysis, Herbert Feigl and Michael Scriven (Eds.) Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press, 1956Google Scholar
Sellars, W.. (1960/1963). “Philosophy and the scientific image of man.” Science, perception and reality. Atascadero, CA, Ridgeview Publishing Company, 1–40Google Scholar
Smart, J. J. C. (1962). Sensations and brain processes. The philosophy of mind. V. C. Chappell (Ed.) Englewood Cliffs, NJ, Prentice-Hall. (This is a slightly revised version of a paper first published in The Philosophical Review, 68, 1959, 141–56.)Google Scholar
Smolensky, P. (1988). “On the proper treatment of connectionism.” Behavior & Brain Sciences 11(1): 1–23CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sorell, T. (1991). Scientism: Philosophy and the infatuation with science. London, RoutledgeCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilkes, K. (1984). “Pragmatics in science and theory in common sense.” Inquiry 27: 339–61CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×