Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-84b7d79bbc-7nlkj Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-27T16:31:01.922Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false
This chapter is part of a book that is no longer available to purchase from Cambridge Core

1 - Introduction

from Part I

Edwin Mares
Affiliation:
Victoria University of Wellington
Get access

Summary

What is a priori knowledge?

Consider the statement “Every coloured thing is extended in space”. This seems obviously true. If we think about some things that have no length or breadth or depth, we see that they have no colours. Examples of such things are individual points in space and, at least according to traditional philosophy, thoughts. A point cannot have any colour and neither can a thought (although, of course, we can think about colours). But surveying such objects seems unnecessary. We do not have to check everything that has a colour to discover whether it is extended in space. It seems that we can just know this by thinking about it. Traditionally, philosophers have said that this is something that we can know a priori, that is, we can know it independently of experience. Thus, some philosophers say that we can know a priori that every coloured thing is extended. Our knowledge in this case is supposedly independent of experience.

Let us look at another example. Think of a geometrical figure with three straight sides. Let it also be closed: do not allow any gaps in it. How many angles does this figure have? You know the answer: it has three angles. You do not need to check real three-sided figures to make sure they have three angles. From a consideration of the nature of three-sided figures alone, you can know that they all have three angles. This is a priori reasoning.

Type
Chapter
Information
A Priori , pp. 1 - 12
Publisher: Acumen Publishing
Print publication year: 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Introduction
  • Edwin Mares, Victoria University of Wellington
  • Book: A Priori
  • Online publication: 05 February 2013
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/UPO9781844652860.002
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Introduction
  • Edwin Mares, Victoria University of Wellington
  • Book: A Priori
  • Online publication: 05 February 2013
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/UPO9781844652860.002
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Introduction
  • Edwin Mares, Victoria University of Wellington
  • Book: A Priori
  • Online publication: 05 February 2013
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/UPO9781844652860.002
Available formats
×