Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-gq7q9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-16T12:53:15.024Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false
This chapter is part of a book that is no longer available to purchase from Cambridge Core

4 - Representationalism: representations as natural signs

Barry Maund
Affiliation:
University of Western Austrailia
Get access

Summary

We can, I have argued, identify primary cases of perception as ones that involve the acquiring of knowledge, both practical and theoretical. Both kinds of knowledge are what might be called “object-based knowledge” and involve knowledge by acquaintance. The practical knowledge is manifested in a variety of ways: in locating the object in space, discriminating the object from its background and in targeting one's action on the object, for example, in grasping, touching or pushing the object in question.

The description of object-based knowledge in this context suggests that the right theory of perception is some version of direct realism, and that indirect, representative theories are ruled out. This suggestion, I shall argue, ought to be resisted. It is possible, however, to formulate a representative theory of perception that will handle this kind of perceptual knowledge, a hybrid theory, to be more accurate, that contains direct and indirect components.

Direct and indirect theories of perception

One of the central questions in the philosophy of perception is whether perception is direct or indirect. This question historically has been framed within the context of the debate between direct realist theories of perception, and the representative theory of perception (representational realism), where the latter is understood as committed to indirect realism. The contrast is typically registered in the following way:

  • Indirect realism/representational realism: The perceiver perceives physical objects and states of affairs indirectly by perceiving immediately or directly other items, standardly sensory particulars or states of affairs.

  • Direct realism: The perceiver perceives immediately (or directly) physical objects and states of affairs without perceiving any intermediary.

Type
Chapter
Information
Perception , pp. 67 - 88
Publisher: Acumen Publishing
Print publication year: 2002

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×