Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-8zxtt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-12T17:31:45.607Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false
This chapter is part of a book that is no longer available to purchase from Cambridge Core

Mathesis Universalis and the Life-World: Finitude and Responsibility

from Articles

Burt Hopkins
Affiliation:
Seattle University
John Drummond
Affiliation:
Fordham University
Get access

Summary

Abstract: Scientific philosophy has a “critical” meaning, from the first-person perspective, and a “dogmatic” meaning, from the third-person perspective. “Objectively” oriented philosophy finds its highest degree of rationalization in symbolic thought, and ultimately in a mathesis universalis. Although its development entails a depletion of its meaning-fundament in the life-world, it serves the purpose of compensating for the finitude of human cognition. Yet critical philosophy, not satisfied with this “natural” orientation, interrogates the essential origin of every positive formal science in finite experience. Husserl's relative concept of evidence is not a skeptical one and does not exclude the idea of “truth in itself.” His “transcendental relativism” refers to the self-responsibility of the radical scientific philosopher bent on the resolution of “all conceivable problems in philosophy,” in an ongoing teleological process of infinite tasks.

Keywords: formalization, critical phenomenology, life-world, philosophical self-responsibility, mathesis universalis

The Twofold Sense of Scientific Philosophy

For Husserl scientific philosophy ultimately has a twofold sense. On the one hand, it is developed within a “subjective” or first-person perspective and is radical or “critical” insofar as it attempts to disclose the philosophical origin of the positive sciences. Thus, it seeks to clarify both how their concepts, laws, and theories, as well as their objects, can become manifest “for us” if they are essentially “in themselves” and how, entering the flux of lived experience, they can be thought, expressed, and applied to experience without thereby losing their objectivity and transcendent meaning.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Acumen Publishing
Print publication year: 2013

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×