Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-8ctnn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-29T01:58:36.235Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

11 - Choosing treatments and the role of shared decision-making

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 July 2020

Ellen Nolte
Affiliation:
London School of Hygiene and Tropical Medicine
Sherry Merkur
Affiliation:
European Observatory on Health Systems and Policies
Anders Anell
Affiliation:
Lunds Universitet, Sweden
Jonathan North
Affiliation:
European Observatory on Health Systems and Policies

Summary

In 2015 people in OECD countries consulted a medical practitioner between two and sixteen times (OECD, 2015). These care-seekers were once expected to go along with whatever the doctor decided was best, but this has been slowly changing since the 1970s. As highlighted in Chapter 2 of this book, growing awareness of the limits of medical interventions and of the lack of control over decisions about one’s own care (Illich, 1975) led to calls for equality between the patient and the health professional towards establishing a partnership for making decisions and determining the direction of care.

The notion of a more participatory approach to informed decision-making was first proposed by Robert Veatch in 1972, who suggested the idea of “sharing of decision-making” (Veatch, 1972). Evidence was accumulating that where doctors and patients agreed on the problem, outcomes were better (Starfield et al., 1979).

Type
Chapter
Information
Achieving Person-Centred Health Systems
Evidence, Strategies and Challenges
, pp. 283 - 316
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2020
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NCCreative Common License - ND
This content is Open Access and distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence CC-BY-NC-ND 4.0 https://creativecommons.org/cclicenses/

Introduction

In 2015 people in OECD countries consulted a medical practitioner between two and sixteen times (OECD, 2015). These care-seekers were once expected to go along with whatever the doctor decided was best, but this has been slowly changing since the 1970s. As highlighted in Chapter 2 of this book, growing awareness of the limits of medical interventions and of the lack of control over decisions about one’s own care (Reference IllichIllich, 1975) led to calls for equality between the patient and the health professional towards establishing a partnership for making decisions and determining the direction of care.

The notion of a more participatory approach to informed decision-making was first proposed by Robert Veatch in 1972, who suggested the idea of “sharing of decision-making” (Reference VeatchVeatch, 1972). Evidence was accumulating that where doctors and patients agreed on the problem, outcomes were better (Reference StarfieldStarfield et al., 1979). In 1982 a US presidential commission noted that while health care systems were increasingly effective at addressing disease, there was a “diminished capacity and inclination to care for the patient in more human terms” (President’s Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research, 1982, p. 33). These observations came at a time when there was increasing recognition of practice variations (Reference WennbergWennberg & Gittelsohn, 1973) and of unnecessary surgery (Reference LeapeLeape, 1989) across the USA. Neither of these could be explained by variation in the burden of disease or medical need, while evidence pointed to widespread overuse, underuse and misuse of tests and treatments. Policy-makers finally began to take note, and shared decision-making was proposed as one potential solution. The US Presidential Commission stated that “[p]ractitioners should seek not only to understand each patient’s needs and develop reasonable alternatives to meet those needs but also … present the alternatives in a way that enables patients to choose one they prefer. To participate in this process, patients must engage in a dialogue with the practitioner and make their views on well-being clear” (President’s Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research, 1982, p. 44). Shared decision-making (SDM) was seen to be especially appropriate with regard to ‘preference-sensitive’ conditions (Reference WeinsteinWeinstein, 2000; Reference Weinstein, Clay and MorganWeinstein, Clay & Morgan, 2007). It began to take root as a core approach in primary care and to be considered the crux of person-centred care (Reference WestonWeston, 2001; Reference Charles, Gafni and WhelanCharles, Gafni & Whelan, 1997).

Along with supported self-management (Reference EffingEffing et al., 2007), SDM has now entered government policy and legislation in several countries. Since 1968 more than 6000 articles have been published about the theory and practice of SDM, and as of 2013 over 500 per year (Reference KosterKoster, 2016), indicating an exponential growth of scientific research in this area (Reference BlancBlanc et al., 2014). Much research has focused on studying the impacts of SDM tools (such as decision aids) but there remains a dearth of evidence that takes into account the full complexity of SDM and, more importantly, its implementation in clinical practice (Reference CoulterCoulter, 2017), and physicians have been slow to adopt it (Reference CouetCouet et al., 2015).

With the notion of the relationship at its core, SDM can be defined as an interpersonal, interdependent process in which health professionals, patients and their caregivers relate to and influence each other as they collaborate in making decisions about a patient’s health care (Reference Légaré and WittemanLégaré & Witteman, 2013). Together they consider the scientific evidence and the patient’s preferences and values before making a treatment choice. The information transfer is two-way, and the health professional may not be the only, or even the main, source of information for patients. Patients’ own unique experiences and preferences are equally important for informing the decision, acting as experts in their own right (Reference Charles, Gafni and WhelanCharles, Gafni & Whelan, 1997). It can involve the patient and their family and caregivers (Reference Légaré, Stacey and PouliotLégaré, Stacey & Pouliot, 2011), along with one or more health professionals (often working in teams with patients who have chronic illnesses), as well as other health care workers, for example in the context of community-based primary care and home care (Reference LégaréLégaré et al., 2015).

This chapter begins by setting out the challenges of arriving at a consensual definition of SDM. It discusses how SDM has entered policy debate and legislation and the possible drivers behind this. We examine the empirical evidence for its impact on outcomes at the individual, organizational and system levels, and discuss barriers to its implementation. We discuss models of SDM and how it can be measured, as well as current research trends, and finally propose a framework for a way forward.

How do we define SDM?

SDM is thought to involve three main steps. First, the clinician and the patient recognize and acknowledge that a decision is required, such as making a choice about starting, continuing, stopping or postponing treatment for a given condition. This is called the decision point (Reference CoulterCoulter, 2011), not to be confused with a single point in time, as decisions can be an ongoing event (Reference RapleyRapley, 2008). Second, both parties understand the best available evidence concerning the risks, benefits and consequences of available options, including the option of doing nothing (watchful waiting). Third, the treatment decision reflects the patient’s informed values and preferences about the outcomes of options. For example, a woman with breast cancer may prefer to have conservative breast surgery rather than a mastectomy in the knowledge that survival rates are equivalent (Reference FisherFisher et al., 2002). Or a patient may not want to be prescribed medication, preferring to cope with the condition rather than live with the side-effects of the medication (Reference WeissWeiss et al., 2015). Such decisions can be supported by specifically designed patient decision aids, such as leaflets, videos or web-based tools. Tailored to a person’s health condition, decision aids present the evidence and help clinicians and patients clarify their preferences and values (Reference StaceyStacey et al., 2017). Collections of decision aids can be found at the A to Z Inventory of Decision Aids (Ottawa Hospital Research Institute, 2015) and at the Med-Decs database (Reference StalmeierStalmeier, 2012).

However, as noted, at its core SDM is about relationships and values, and as such it is difficult to define. Reference Charles, Gafni and WhelanCharles, Gafni & Whelan (1997) identified four key components: the patient and the clinician are involved in all phases; both parties share information; both parties take steps to build a consensus about the preferred treatment; and an agreement is reached about the treatment to be implemented. These components have since been renamed, further divided and redefined. However, most definitions still revolve around information exchange, deliberation, making the decision, and follow-up (Reference Makoul and ClaymanMakoul & Clayman, 2006; Reference StaceyStacey et al., 2010; Reference ElwynElwyn et al., 2012; Reference Stiggelbout, Pieterse and De HaesStiggelbout, Pieterse & De Haes, 2015). The single defining feature of SDM remains what Ian McWhinney called the “exchange and synthesis of meanings” (Reference StewartStewart, 2003) that take place in the clinical encounter.

When SDM entered clinical practice, it was typically in the context of ‘professional equipoise’ (Reference Pauker and KassirerPauker & Kassirer, 1997; Reference ElwynElwyn et al., 2000), that is, in situations where the doctor had no clear preference about the best treatment choice. However, more recently SDM has been recognized as desirable in all situations where there is more than one reasonable approach to managing or treating a given condition (including watchful waiting). It is also seen to be useful for eliciting patients’ values, namely what matters to the patients or their family members about the decision, such as efficacy, side-effects and cost, as well as life philosophies, priorities and life circumstances (Reference Weinstein, Clay and MorganWeinstein, Clay & Morgan, 2007; Reference Lee, Low and NgLee, Low & Ng, 2013). Even where probabilities of risks and benefits of a given treatment are known for the population as a whole, these do not automatically translate to the individual, and the importance attached to risks and benefits may differ among individual patients, depending on their values and preferences.

While SDM is widely seen to be core to person-centred care (Reference CoulterCoulter, 2017), some authors have taken a more cautious approach. For example, some authors have noted that SDM has been used to make patients uniquely responsible for their health (care) choices, with health professionals no longer being held accountable for decisions (Reference Tobias and SouhamiTobias & Souhami, 1993; Reference Buetow and KenealyBuetow & Kenealy, 2007; Reference Sandman, Gustavsson and MuntheSandman, Gustavsson & Munthe, 2016). Others noted that patients do not necessarily want to involve clinicians in decisions (Reference Degner and SloanDegner & Sloan, 1992) or prefer that the clinician makes treatment decisions on their behalf (Reference WoolfWoolf, 2001; Reference SchattnerSchattner, 2002). Yet others argued that SDM can make patients feel anxious and insecure (Reference LevyLevy et al., 1989; Reference CaldonCaldon et al., 2011; Reference West and WestWest & West, 2002) and there have been concerns that SDM might inadvertently favour those with higher education and disadvantage those who are already marginalized, thus reinforcing health inequities (Reference Thomson, Murtagh and KhawThomson, Murtagh & Khaw, 2005). We shall come back to these concerns later.

How has SDM entered law and policy?

There is now increasing consensus that there is an ethical imperative for health professionals to share important decisions with patients (Salzburg Global Reference SeminarSeminar, 2011). In recognition, many countries in Europe, North America and Australia (Reference Härter, van der Weijden and ElwynHärter, van der Weijden & Elwyn, 2011) have put in place formal recognition of SDM in the form of policy and regulatory frameworks as part of a wider move towards more person-centred systems. Elsewhere, the importance of SDM is increasingly being considered, with a small number of countries in South America and south-east Asia slowly introducing related policies (Reference HärterHärter et al., 2017b). Their rationale ranges from respect for consumer and patient rights and democratic public engagement to more instrumental arguments such as that it might increase efficiency and help control health care costs (Reference Gibson, Britten and LynchGibson, Britten & Lynch, 2012).

Most European countries are legislating on informed consent and patients’ right to information using civil law (e.g. the Netherlands) or public law (e.g. Finland) (see Chapter 13). Other countries have dedicated elements of their national or regional legislation specifically to their interpretations of SDM. These include France (2002 Act on Patients’ Rights and Quality of Care) (République Reference FrançaiseFrançaise, 2002), Chile (2006 Law on Rights and Responsibilities of People when Engaging in their Healthcare) (Reference BravoBravo et al., 2011), Norway (1999 Patients’ Rights Act) (Reference RingardRingard et al., 2013), Sweden (2015 Patient Act) (Riksdag, 2014) (Box 11.1), Germany (Patients’ Rights Act) (Bundesministerium für Gesundheit, 2013), the UK (2012 Health and Social Care Act) (Government of the United Kingdom, 2012), and the United States (2010 Patient Protection and Affordable Care Act) (US Congress, 2010). Elsewhere, patients’ rights to information and participation in their own care are recognized across a broad diversity of legislation, such as in Italy and Denmark (Reference TragakesTragakes et al., 2008; Reference Dahl Steffensen, Hjelholt Baker and VinterDahl Steffensen, Hjelholt Baker & Vinter, 2017).

Box 11.1 Excerpt from the 2015 Patient Act, Sweden

“Caregivers are required to provide you with all necessary information no matter who you are or what background you have . . . The information must be adapted to your particular circumstances and capabilities . . . You must always have the chance to explain what you want to happen – then it is up to you to decide how much you want to take advantage of that opportunity. Once you are familiar with the options that are available, you can give your consent or otherwise indicate your preferences. You are always entitled to turn down any care that is offered to you. You can also change your mind after you have approved a certain kind of care.”

SDM legislation facilitates the appropriate application of the so-called ‘reasonable patient standard’. The standard for informed consent is typically physician-based. This means that clinicians must provide patients with the information that a so-called ‘responsible body of physicians’ would consider appropriate under similar circumstances (Reference MoultonMoulton et al., 2013). However, this is slowly changing, with for example approximately half of the states in the USA having adopted ‘the reasonable patient standard’ instead (Reference Spatz, Krumholz and MoultonSpatz, Krumholz & Moulton, 2016). This views the informed consent communication process from the patient’s perspective, that is, clinicians must provide patients with all the information that a ‘reasonable patient’ would want under similar circumstances. Case law based on this standard has also been applied in Australia, Canada, the Netherlands and the United Kingdom (Box 11.2), whereas elsewhere in Europe the notion of the ‘reasonable body of physicians’ standard prevails. The importance of establishing the ‘reasonable patient’ as the standard in the context of SDM can be illustrated by Washington State in the USA. Washington State is among the US states where informed consent has been patient-based since a key court case in 1999 (Reference King and MoultonKing & Moulton, 2006). In 2007 it introduced legislation that supports the use of SDM and it also provided that if a clinician uses a ‘certified decision aid’ as part of the informed consent process, there is a presumption that informed consent has been given (Washington State Health Care Authority, 2016). Thus, the context of the ‘reasonable patient’ as the norm facilitated the introduction of explicit SDM legislation. This suggests that a similar move would be necessary in Europe if SDM is to be implemented on a large scale.

Box 11.2 A reasonable patient

Montgomery v Lanarkshire Health Board, 2015, UK. A woman with insulin-dependent diabetes claimed that her obstetrician failed to communicate the risk of shoulder dystocia during vaginal delivery (a complication associated with foetal macrosomia) that ultimately resulted in severe foetal brain anoxia. She claimed that had she received full information about the risks, she would have opted for a caesarean delivery. Yet the treating obstetrician (and other expert physicians called to trial) claimed that the ensuing risk was very small and thus appropriately not communicated, because a caesarean delivery is not in the maternal interest. The UK Supreme Court ruled that the standard for what physicians should inform patients about the risks, benefits and alternatives of treatment ‘will no longer be determined by what a responsible body of physicians deems important but rather by what a reasonable patient deems important’.

However, available evidence suggests that while countries in Europe are engaging in a variety of activities conducive to the wider implementation of SDM, system-wide approaches to translating SDM into routine practice are as yet lacking. Reference CoulterCoulter et al. (2015) assessed the readiness for SDM in five European countries by examining clinical policies and the availability of various SDM support services in France, Germany, the Netherlands, Spain and the UK in 2015. They found that while SDM was receiving growing attention, it was not yet as high on the policy agenda as it was in the USA at the time. There was evidence of research activity around SDM, increasing advocacy by patient groups on patient rights and SDM, and the incorporation of SDM in ethical and professional standards. But there was a lack of professional leadership and of institutional support. Furthermore, countries varied greatly with regard to the development and availability of SDM tools. Some had been developed and tested with patients locally but mostly in the context of research, with little institutional support or strategic planning for wider dissemination.

Reference CoulterCoulter et al. (2015) further highlighted that the training infrastructure necessary for clinical staff to acquire SDM skills was patchy in the countries studied. While SDM was beginning to be included in basic communication skills training, it was not yet implemented as a core component of health professional education and training. This situation is now changing in some countries, such as in the Netherlands and Germany, where SDM is taught and examined in most medical schools, although on a limited scale (Reference van der Weijdenvan der Weijden et al., 2017; Reference HärterHärter et al., 2017a). In Switzerland, all five medical schools (Basel, Bern, Geneva, Lausanne and Zürich) have formally integrated SDM into both undergraduate and postgraduate training (general internal medicine) (Reference Selby, Auer and CornuzSelby, Auer & Cornuz, 2017).

SDM is a fast-moving field and, in addition to educational progress, efforts to develop strategic policy frameworks for SDM are under way across Europe. Thus the Netherlands has seen a range of policy moves to a more systematic implementation of SDM at the national level, as exemplified by a 2015 letter to Parliament from the Minister of Health (Rijksoverheid, 2015). The Ministry of Health is introducing a specific registration code to finance additional time needed for SDM, and forthcoming amendments to the Medical Treatment Agreement Act will require physicians to inform the patient about risks and benefits and discuss treatment options (Reference van der Weijdenvan der Weijden et al., 2017). In addition, the national associations of medical specialists and of patients and consumers are campaigning together to promote nationwide implementation of SDM (Federatie Medisch Reference SpecialistenSpecialisten, 2015).

Similarly, SDM is now firmly on the policy agenda in the UK, with policy-makers, professional regulators and societies, and patient organizations, as well as the courts, committed to ensuring that SDM becomes the norm throughout the National Health Service (NHS) (Reference CoulterCoulter et al., 2017). A key challenge has been the coordination of various activities and initiatives and in 2015 over 40 organizations came together to form the SDM Collaborative, led by the National Institute for Health and Care Excellence (NICE). The Collaborative has published an SDM consensus statement and an action plan which sets out actions taken by individual partners in the short- and medium term (National Institute for Health and Care Excellence, 2016).

Progress has been somewhat slower in France, despite having the legal foundations in place for system-wide strengthening of SDM, in particular through the aforementioned 2002 Act on Patients’ Rights and Quality of Care. The 2016 health reform provided for the introduction of a public information service which seeks to disseminate information on health, and especially on treatment, care and support offered to the public (Reference MoumjidMoumjid et al., 2017). Under the responsibility of the Minister for Health, the information should be in simple language and accessible for people with disabilities.

Finally, a number of countries, including the UK, the Netherlands, Germany and Norway, have invested in initiatives to make patient decision aids available to some extent (Reference CoulterCoulter et al., 2017; Reference van der Weijdenvan der Weijden et al., 2017; Reference HärterHärter et al., 2017a; Reference RingardRingard et al., 2013). For example, in the UK NICE hosts 27 (as of August 2017) short-form patient decision aids to help patients have informed conversations about their condition with their health care provider (NHS Reference RightcareRightCare, 2017; NHS Reference EnglandEngland, n/d). In the Netherlands, the national associations of medical specialists and of patients host publicly available patient decision aids on national patient portals (Reference van der Weijdenvan der Weijden et al., 2017). In Germany, the Institute for Quality and Efficiency in Health Care (IQWiG) recently developed three decision aids for the national breast, colon and cervical cancer screening programmes in response to requests from the Federal Joint Committee, the highest decision-making body in the German statutory health insurance system (Reference HärterHärter et al., 2017a).

Despite this progress in implementing SDM in European countries, considerable barriers remain. For SDM to become a standard approach in the clinical encounter, there is a need for professional organizations to incorporate patient decision support tools in clinical practice guidelines and, more broadly, for policy-makers and institutions to support local clinicians in the routine implementation of SDM (Reference CoulterCoulter et al., 2015). We will return to the issue of what needs to be done later.

What does SDM achieve?

Shared decision-making has been associated with a number of expectations, ranging from improving population health outcomes, reducing health inequalities, optimizing health care costs, improving patient experiences, and increasing patient knowledge or engagement in their own care, to reducing litigation. Whether SDM is likely to achieve any of these expected outcomes depends on a range of factors, which we review here.

Overall, the principal conviction underlying SDM is that clinicians must both honour the patient’s self-determination and offer a relationship of support, that is, SDM recognizes both autonomy and interdependence as key motivators. It also recognizes the importance of sharing the probabilistic nature of evidence and it recognizes that both emotional and cognitive factors play a role. These ‘dualities’ are reflected in many studies of SDM. Early evidence found that a relationship of mutual respect or equality between the patient and doctor during the decision-making process increases patient satisfaction (Reference Menzel, Coleman and KatzMenzel, Coleman & Katz, 1959). These early findings have been replicated elsewhere, with recent systematic review evidence demonstrating that SDM may have a positive impact on affective-cognitive patient outcomes, such as knowledge, satisfaction with care, and concerns/anxieties about the illness (Reference Shay and LafataShay & Lafata, 2015). Compared to patients who did not reach agreement with their health professionals on certain key components of the clinical encounter, those who did reach an agreement felt more satisfied with the clinical encounter (Reference KrupatKrupat et al., 2001).

These kinds of outcome are important. Research on decision-making has shown that personal decision-making involves a negotiation process with the ‘outside world’ which encompasses more than cognition. However, much SDM work has focused on cognition (e.g. knowledge, understanding) rather than emotion. Emotional factors such as trust, reassurance and comfort influence intermediate outcomes including adherence (Reference SewitchSewitch et al., 2003) and self-care skills, which in turn influence health outcomes (Reference StreetStreet et al., 2009). These factors could also, in part, explain differences between decisions made in natural contexts and those made in experimental contexts (Reference RapleyRapley et al., 2006).

There is a fundamental ethical argument for involving patients in decisions about their own care and treatment, since it is their body and their illness, and so it is their aspirations, values and preferences that should be addressed. Evidence suggests that patients generally want more information about their health condition and would like to take an active role in decisions about their care (Reference AlstonAlston et al., 2012; Reference Kiesler and AuerbachKiesler & Auerbach, 2006). However, the degree to which a decision is shared varies widely in terms of the underlying health problem, the treatment or care options and the actors involved, including the patients themselves (Reference Hagbaghery, Salsali and AhmadiHagbaghery, Salsali & Ahmadi, 2004; Reference Joseph-Williams, Edwards and ElwynJoseph-Williams, Edwards & Elwyn, 2014).

In terms of reducing health inequalities, systematic review evidence suggests that SDM significantly increases knowledge among disadvantaged groups, as well as their clarity about their values and preferences, although evidence is less clear on impacts on adherence levels, anxiety and health outcomes, as well as on screening/treatment preferences, intentions or uptake (Reference DurandDurand et al., 2014). Others observed that reducing the patient/clinician power differential is essential before most patients feel comfortable or competent to engage in SDM (Reference Joseph-Williams, Edwards and ElwynJoseph-Williams, Edwards & Elwyn, 2014).

In some countries litigation is a major concern, and Reference DurandDurand et al. (2015) found that poor communication is strongly correlated with medical malpractice litigation. However, based on a synthesis of five studies, they concluded that there is insufficient evidence to determine whether SDM reduces medical malpractice litigation. Nevertheless, effective decision support can lead to decreased decisional conflict (i.e. personal uncertainty regarding one’s choice) and some evidence suggests that if SDM is applied, patients appear to be more satisfied and more compliant with the treatment they have agreed upon, which is likely to reduce the risk of litigation (Reference Ubbink, Santema and LapidUbbink, Santema & Lapid, 2016).

Among health professionals in particular, there is widespread concern about the time required for implementing SDM in routine clinical care (Reference LégaréLégaré et al., 2008). The belief that it will lengthen consultations is so pervasive that the Dutch government proposes to compensate clinicians for the additional time they perceive they would need to implement it, as noted above. Yet although consultation lengths vary depending on the context, there is no definitive evidence that SDM systematically requires more time than usual care (Reference LégaréLégaré et al., 2012b; Légaré et al., 2018) except in palliative care contexts (Reference StaceyStacey et al., 2017). Furthermore, any additional time spent on SDM may be recouped if patients return less frequently.

Among policy-makers another prime concern is the effective use of scarce resources. There are inherent challenges in assessing the cost-effectiveness of SDM, and robust evidence that SDM may lead to system-wide savings is lacking (Reference WalshWalsh et al., 2014; Reference Trenaman, Bryan and BansbackTrenaman, Bryan & Bansback, 2014). A systematic review of the effects of decision aids for people facing treatment or screening decisions found that patients who were better informed and had been given an opportunity to weigh up the risks of treatment options tended to choose more conservative options (Reference StaceyStacey et al., 2017). Based on such observations, there is an expectation among policy-makers that decision support tools can reduce overuse of costly services and treatments (Reference Elwyn, Tilburt and MontoriElwyn, Tilburt & Montori, 2013). There is indeed a persuasive argument that providing care that is informed and consistent with people’s values can lead to more appropriate use of resources (Reference ElwynMulley, Trimble & Elwyn, 2012). However, if SDM is an ethical imperative (Box 11.3), and patients value being involved in the decision-making process, the promise of significant savings should not be a condition for its implementation, and indeed could jeopardize implementation efforts (Reference WalshWalsh et al., 2014; Reference Sandman, Gustavsson and MuntheSandman, Gustavsson & Munthe, 2016).

Box 11.3 The ethical imperative for shared decision-making

“The benefits of shared decision-making to Society will accrue by the accumulated trust that the profession engenders through daily interactions that demonstrate unequivocal fidelity to the dignity and values of informed patients. We do not advocate the abrogation of professional roles: it will remain necessary for physicians to disagree, even argue, respectfully, with patients, provided patients’ views are taken seriously. But, as clinicians invite and welcome patient involvement, it is also essential to share in the work of making difficult decisions, not to abandon patients at the fork in the road.”

What practical tools support SDM?

Patient decision aids are the principal tool used to support SDM. In a review of 105 studies involving 31 043 patients, Reference StaceyStacey et al. (2017) showed that those who engaged in SDM and received a decision aid (either written, electronic, audio-visual or web-based tool formats) had greater knowledge of the evidence, felt clearer about what mattered to them, had more accurate expectations about the risks and benefits, and participated more in the decision-making process compared to those receiving usual care. Yet as noted earlier in this chapter, while there has been tremendous progress in the development of patient decision aids, including a generic decision aid (Ottawa Hospital Research Institute, 2015) that can be adapted to any health-related or social decision (Reference ArimoriArimori, 2006; Reference SaarimakiSaarimaki, 2013), it is unlikely that decision aids will be created for every decision and in every language. Also, their implementation remains challenging, in particular where the process is disconnected from the routine workflow or from the wider system context (Reference Elwyn, Frosch and KobrinElwyn, Frosch & Kobrin, 2016). The fundamental need is still for skilled clinicians to have the right conversations with patients (Reference Kunneman and MontoriKunneman & Montori, 2016). Patient decision aids and other tools can facilitate the conversation, but they cannot replace it.

A significant body of work has focused on training health professionals in SDM. While there remains lack of consensus on the precise components of SDM (Reference Shay and LafataShay & Lafata, 2014; Reference LégaréLégaré et al., 2013; Reference Légaré and WittemanLégaré & Witteman, 2013), there is agreement that risk communication skills can be learned by clinicians, both in their professional training and continuing professional education. Such training programmes for practitioners are becoming increasingly common (Reference DioufDiouf et al., 2016), with their effectiveness often measured in terms of changes in clinicians’ behaviours and patient experiences (Reference Al-Janabi, Flynn and CoastAl-Janabi, Flynn & Coast, 2012).

A 2018 Cochrane review of the effectiveness of interventions to improve health professionals’ adoption of SDM found the overall evidence to be of low quality, with uncertainty about what type of intervention works best or what their key components should be (Légaré et al., 2018). It did suggest that interventions that simultaneously target both the health professional (e.g. training) and the patient (e.g. decision aids) are likely to be more effective than each on their own. Reference LégaréLégaré et al. (2013) identified the range of core competencies clinicians should acquire for effectively involving patients in health-related decisions. These include being aware of patients’ information needs, knowing how to communicate relevant information, nondirective interviewing, risk communication, eliciting patients’ preferences, personalized care planning, and self-management support. They also include learning to use patient decision aids (Reference StaceyStacey et al., 2013) or clinical tools such as SURE to screen for decisional comfort (Reference LégaréLégaré et al., 2010).

In summary, while promising, the existing evidence base on the effectiveness of SDM remains somewhat ambiguous or, with respect to certain outcomes such as cost savings, in need of more research. Evidence points to positive outcomes at the individual level but there are large gaps in the evidence about outcomes at the clinical, organizational and systems level, largely because of a lack of implementation at these levels (Reference Elwyn, Frosch and KobrinElwyn, Frosch & Kobrin, 2016). Existing measures are still under development, as we discuss below. Perhaps a more fundamental and still unresolved question is what and who defines a ‘good decision’, and how to evaluate it (Reference HamiltonHamilton et al., 2017), an issue discussed in some detail in Chapter 4 of this book.

What are the barriers to implementing SDM?

We established earlier that SDM is recognized as the core of person-centred care and is increasingly present in health care policy and legislation worldwide. Yet widespread implementation of SDM in routine practice (Reference CouetCouet et al., 2015) or at a system level (Reference Elwyn, Tilburt and MontoriElwyn et al., 2013) remains the exception. We have also noted that patient decision aids are a helpful tool in SDM, and numerous accredited patient decision aids are available (Reference VolkVolk et al., 2013). Yet patient decision aids are not widely used in clinical practice and few people are even aware they exist (Reference LepineLepine et al., 2016).

The evidence points to a number of barriers that hamper the routine implementation of SDM in clinical practice. We have highlighted the many real or perceived barriers noted by health care providers, such as time constraints to actively engage in SDM, or attitudes, such as the belief that patients want decisions made for them, or not being in the habit of engaging their patients in SDM (Reference LégaréLégaré et al., 2006; Reference Godolphin, Towle and McKendryGodolphin, Towle & McKendry, 2001; Reference Makoul, Arntson and SchofieldMakoul, Arntson & Schofield, 1995). Perhaps clinicians are reluctant because they were trained to relieve and protect patients from anxiety-provoking information (Reference TudiverTudiver et al., 2002). Further, patients might ask for a treatment option that the clinician does not consider beneficial and the clinician may be concerned about potential malpractice litigation (Reference Zikmund-FisherZikmund-Fisher et al., 2016), although there is no conclusive evidence about the latter, as noted earlier (Reference DurandDurand et al., 2015).

There are also barriers on the part of the patient, who may not want to engage in SDM. The evidence on patient preferences about participating in decision-making is very mixed, for reasons we do not yet fully understand (Reference ChewningChewning et al., 2012). The role patients wish to play in the decision may depend on the type of health problem, on personal characteristics (Reference ThompsonThompson, 2007), or on the level of trust between the patient and the physician: the lower the trust, the less the patient feels comfortable in engaging in the process (Reference KraetschmerKraetschmer et al., 2004). Also, attitudes and behaviours are slow to change. Thus even where clinicians wish to implement SDM, their communication skills may be inadequate (Reference Stiggelbout, Pieterse and De HaesStiggelbout, Pieterse & De Haes, 2015). In addition, patients are often reluctant to question their doctors because they worry this will be perceived as challenging the clinician’s expertise (‘being difficult’), which might, in turn, negatively impact the quality of care the patient will receive in the future (Reference AdamsAdams et al., 2012; Reference FroschFrosch et al., 2012).

The inconsistent evidence base about the benefits and risks of SDM and consequent lack of confidence in SDM interventions might also reduce decision-makers’ support for relevant strategies, as might the overlap in terminology between patient engagement and SDM and the conceptual vagueness surrounding its key concepts (Reference LégaréLégaré et al., 2013; Reference Légaré and WittemanLégaré & Witteman, 2013). Moreover, a set of best practices for SDM has yet to be agreed upon, and many of the underlying barriers themselves, such as clinician indifference, remain under-investigated (Reference Elwyn, Tilburt and MontoriElwyn et al., 2013).

Perhaps a more fundamental challenge relates to the issue of power, a challenge highlighted elsewhere in this volume (see Chapters 4, 5, 6 and 12). SDM requires an explicit sharing of power and knowledge in a relationship that has traditionally been characterized by an imbalance of power in favour of the clinician (Reference Joseph-Williams, Edwards and ElwynJoseph-Williams, Edwards & Elwyn, 2014). In many cultures there is a strong hierarchy of authority which is not openly challenged, at personal, institutional or political levels (Reference Rahimi, Alizadeh and LégaréRahimi, Alizadeh & Légaré, 2017), and this also applies to significant subcultures in western liberal societies (Reference Coleman-Brueckheimer, Spitzer and KoffmanColeman-Brueckheimer, Spitzer & Koffman, 2009; Reference MeadMead et al., 2013). There is a need for researchers to develop patient decision aids and models that are flexible enough to be adapted to a variety of cultures, involving stakeholders from diverse backgrounds and paying particular attention to categories of patients who find risk–benefit information challenging. SDM training should also include considerations of health literacy and cultural competencies, and should increase awareness of variation in patient preferences (Hawley & Morris, 2016; Reference AldenAlden et al., 2014).

Much of the work on SDM has focused on patients’ and clinicians’ attitudes to and engagement in SDM. Conversely, little is known about policy-makers’ views on and understanding of SDM, despite their key role in developing strategies necessary for its widespread implementation. Little is known, too, about the views of health care organizations, which might be reluctant to invest in SDM as it may involve changing established work patterns or provider tasks (Reference Elwyn, Frosch and KobrinElwyn, Frosch & Kobrin, 2016). Some countries have changed financial incentives for providers towards value-based payment methods that seek to optimize health outcomes for the patient per dollar spent (Reference PorterPorter, 2010). There is increasing experimentation with, for example, pay-for-performance schemes, capitation and bundled payment arrangements or accountable care organizations to strengthen care coordination and hold health care providers to account for delivering high quality care (Reference Anell and GlenngårdAnell & Glenngård, 2014; Reference Nolte, Knai and SaltmanNolte, Knai & Saltman, 2014; Reference Kronick, Casalino and BindmanKronick, Casalino & Bindman, 2015), and SDM could at least theoretically be built into such payment systems. However, such approaches are highly complex, requiring careful design, relevant measures and indicators, and consideration of the context in which the payment system is introduced. The risk is that such systems can be distorted by uncontrollable factors such as patients’ socioeconomic status, or measures that are inadequate for the task. For example, attribution (which doctors are responsible for which patient outcomes?) must factor in risk-adjustment and randomness or else physicians will be incentivized to avoid patients with multi-morbidities, who are exceptionally high users of hospital services (Reference Anell and GlenngårdAnell & Glenngård, 2014). Without institutional consensus on what constitutes value and quality in health care, measurement might simply reflect what physicians, politicians or accountants value, rather than what patients value (Reference Mannion and BraithwaiteMannion & Braithwaite, 2012).

How should we measure SDM?

Many reviews have shown that SDM processes and outcomes are difficult to quantify (Reference ElwynElwyn et al., 2001; Reference DyDy, 2007; Reference LégaréLégaré et al., 2007; Reference Simon, Loh and HarterSimon, Loh & Harter, 2007; Reference KryworuchkoKryworuchko et al., 2008; Reference SchollScholl et al., 2011; Reference Sepucha and SchollSepucha & Scholl, 2014). Identifying relevant theoretical models for SDM, evaluating interventions in clinical practice and measuring their impact (including cost-effectiveness) remain the subject of ongoing research in this relatively young field.

The kinds of outcome researchers seek primarily reflect the expectations of those assessing SDM. Where patient engagement is built into legislation (such as the Affordable Care Act in the USA), health care administrators seek reliable and valid system level measures that allow conclusions about the impacts of SDM strategies on population health. A major impediment to the more rapid spread of SDM may be that there are not yet enough system measures that can be effectively and efficiently tracked by health care organizations. Much research has explored more process-oriented outcomes, for example measures of the patient’s role in decision-making (Reference Conway, Mostashari and ClancyConway, Mostashari & Clancy, 2013).

Those who are interested in clinical practice may focus their research on the creation of brief tools, such as the three-question CollaboRATE (Box 11.4), which measures efforts made by the clinical team to engage them in decision-making as reported by patients (Reference BarrBarr et al., 2014).

Several conceptual frameworks have been proposed for measuring SDM. The most comprehensive and commonly used model was designed by Makoul & Clayman, and it identifies nine essential constructs that describe the observable features of SDM in a consultation (Reference Makoul and ClaymanMakoul & Clayman, 2006; Reference ClaymanClayman et al., 2012). Using this framework, Reference Bouniols, Leclère and MoretBouniols, Leclère & Moret (2016) reviewed and mapped validated SDM measurement tools and found that none of the identified tools mapped on all the nine elements described by Makoul & Clayman, although all measured three of the elements (‘define/explain problem’, ‘patient values/preferences’, and ‘check/clarify understanding’). The MAPPIN’ SDM instrument and SDM’Mass developed by Kasper and colleagues (Reference KasperKasper et al., 2012; Reference KasperGeiger & Kasper, 2012) cover eight of the components.

Box 11.4 The CollaboRATE tool: a three-item patient-reported measure of SDM

The CollaboRATE tool consists of three items.

Thinking about the appointment you have just had:

  1. 1. How much effort was made to help you understand your health issues?

  2. 2. How much effort was made to listen to the things that matter most to you about your health issues?

  3. 3. How much effort was made to include what matters most to you in choosing what to do next?

Responses to each item can range from 0 (No effort was made) to 9 (Every effort was made) for a maximum total of 27.

Reference Elwyn, Frosch and KobrinElwyn, Frosch & Kobrin (2016) developed a conceptual framework that hypothesizes a set of outcomes of SDM (or ‘collaborative deliberation’) that considers the ‘reach’ of its consequences. Proximal effects are immediate, for example informed preferences; distal effects are more enduring, such as modified relationships; and distant effects may change service utilization or institutional norms. A different approach was taken by Sepucha and colleagues, whose model for decision-making distinguishes three general constructs across the continuum of the decision-making process (Reference SepuchaSepucha & Mulley, 2009; Reference Sepucha and SchollSepucha & Scholl, 2014):

  • Decision antecedents, or the features of the patient, provider or organization that may influence the decision-making process;

  • Decision-making process or behaviour in the consultation, such as patient involvement in the decision, decisional conflict or the use of patient decision aids; and

  • Decision outcomes, including knowledge, decision regret, decision quality and patient’s experience of care.

Tools to measure decision antecedents at the patient level include the Control Preferences Scale, which evaluates the preferred role of a patient in decision-making (Reference Degner and SloanDegner & Sloan, 1992); the Autonomy Preference Index, which measures patient preferences about their role in decision-making and their desire to be informed; and tools that assess broader patient characteristics such as health literacy (Reference AboumatarAboumatar et al., 2013) and the culture and history of the physician/patient power imbalance. Each of these instruments has its strengths and weaknesses.

Decision-making processes are commonly assessed using the Observing Patient Involvement Scale, or OPTION (Reference ElwynElwyn et al., 2005); two 9-item SDM questionnaires (patient and clinician versions) (Reference KristonKriston et al., 2010; Reference SchollScholl et al., 2012); or the Decisional Conflict Scale (DCS) (Reference O’ConnorO’Connor, 1995). Few process measures adequately capture implementation, and different stakeholders have different perceptions as to whether SDM has occurred (Reference Rodenburg-VandenbusscheRodenburg-Vandenbussche et al., 2015; Reference Shay and LafataShay & Lafata, 2014). Interestingly, only studies in which the patient reported that SDM had occurred (rather than reported by the doctor, or a third observer) found a significant association with improved patient outcomes (Reference StewartStewart, 2001). This finding suggests that the patient’s perspective is critical to the science of measuring SDM.

Decision outcomes are assessed by measuring decision quality, decision satisfaction or decision regret (Reference SepuchaSepucha, Fowler & Mulley, 2004; Reference BrehautBrehaut et al., 2003). Many of these scales have good reliability statistics, but the validity of most tools remains undetermined, especially as far as diverse populations are concerned. In addition, there are important ceiling effects (high-level scores with little variability in both patient-reported outcomes and other process measures). Very few measures are sensitive to changes in outcomes over time (Reference KirwanKirwan et al., 2016; Reference Barr and ElwynBarr & Elwyn, 2015). Finally, there is still a gap between measuring SDM for research purposes and measurement for clinical and policy-oriented purposes.

Some researchers use measurement frameworks to explain the mechanisms underlying SDM behaviours and explore the relationships between the different constructs of sociocognitive models. Many such models posit that behaviour is driven by intention, and that intention has measurable and modifiable determinants (Reference FroschFrosch et al., 2009; Reference DesrochesDesroches et al., 2011).

New theoretical frameworks are expanding our understanding of decision-making but they have yet to demonstrate their applicability. Measures need to be practical, valid and reliable, and developed in consultation with patients. There is a need for wider testing with both exploratory and confirmatory factor analyses, and for revising existing instruments. Scales should be tested for responsiveness before being used in intervention studies. Further work on discriminant validity would enable us to assess if a scale can distinguish between a decision-making process that is unilateral and one that is truly shared. In the best of all possible worlds, a standardization of outcome measures would allow more meaningful cross-study comparisons (Reference SchollScholl et al., 2011; Reference DecaryDecary et al., 2017).

What are the research trends in SDM?

Research on SDM has gone beyond decisions about medical diagnostics and treatments. For example, in the era of personalized medicine SDM is clearly called for concerning decisions about, and follow-up of, genetic tests for predispositions for which data and treatments are not yet available (Reference Katz, Kurian and MorrowKatz, Kurian & Morrow, 2015). Dyadic SDM research now takes into account the mutual influence of the patient and the physician in the consultation (Reference MelbourneMelbourne et al., 2011; Reference CouetCouet et al., 2015; Reference LégaréLégaré et al., 2012a; Reference LeBlancLeBlanc et al., 2009). Research has also moved beyond conceptualizing SDM as a single encounter to broadening research beyond the consultation (Reference RapleyRapley, 2008). SDM has been incorporated into many more decision contexts, such as around loss of functional autonomy (Reference HansonHanson et al., 2011), palliative care (Reference Belanger, Rodriguez and GroleauBelanger, Rodriguez & Groleau, 2011) and mental illness (Reference CoffeyCoffey et al., 2016).

A key development has been the involvement of a wider range of actors in SDM research, such as family caregivers who are closely involved in decisions about the care of relatives, and a wider group of health professionals and social care workers (Reference GarvelinkGarvelink et al., 2016; Reference DeKeyser GanzDeKeyser Ganz et al., 2016). Researchers are developing models, assessment tools, interventions and decision support tools that take into account decisions shared between all these actors (Reference Laidsaar-PowellLaidsaar-Powell et al., 2013; Reference StaceyStacey et al., 2010; Reference GarvelinkGarvelink et al., 2016). A growing team consciousness of SDM could improve resource use and other group-level performance scores (Reference SorberoSorbero et al., 2008), as well as bringing about change in the cultural norms of health care organizations and systems (Reference Elwyn, Frosch and KobrinElwyn, Frosch & Kobrin, 2016), with an increasing volume of work looking specifically at the impact of SDM at the meso and macro levels (Reference Ballard-BarbashBallard-Barbash, 2012).

Identifying better measures for SDM remains a core research area, as demonstrated by the recent application call for measures of SDM by the US-based Agency for Healthcare Research and Quality (Agency for Healthcare Research and Quality, 2016). Much research has been devoted to exploring the relationships between the constructs of various behavioural models and proposing tools that are sensitive to the less rational and more affective aspects of behaviour change (Reference SniehottaSniehotta, 2009; Reference KeldersKelders et al., 2016). Considerable research is also being devoted to developing and measuring the impact of patient decision aids (Reference VolkVolk et al., 2016). Lastly, the contribution of SDM to reducing waste in health care is gaining attention as most industrialized countries face increasing financial constraints (Reference MorganMorgan et al., 2016).

How can we move SDM forward?

Reference Frosch, Carman, Elwyn, Edwards and ThompsonFrosch & Carman (2016) propose a framework of ‘patient and family engagement’ for moving ahead with interventions and policies to implement SDM. Their model envisages a continuum of patient engagement that is applicable to direct patient care, organizational governance and policy development, and yet remains flexible enough to match the capabilities, interests and goals of individual patients (Reference Dy and PurnellDy & Purnell, 2012). It posits that patient values influence not only clinical decisions but also decisions about hospital design, recruitment, quality improvement strategies and policy priorities. The continuum structure of this framework is also responsive to the accumulation of evidence about what works and what does not.

Facilitators for developing such a culture of engagement at the policy level are social and cultural norms that are open to public influence, as well as institutions that are open to public participation, as demonstrated, for example, by state policies responding to public pressure to control the tobacco market (World Health Reference OrganizationOrganization, 2017). The organization, financing and governance of health care systems play a key role (Reference Korda and EldridgeKorda & Eldridge, 2011). Legislation can also facilitate patient engagement by, for example, mandating public advisory councils in hospitals (Reference CarmanCarman et al., 2013).

SDM is only one of the many facets of greater engagement of patients and the wider public in health care at the different tiers of the system. As several contributions to this volume have shown, fostering an engagement culture at all levels and including civil society is essential if equal partnerships and effective relationships between patients and professionals are to be translated into a reality. SDM is mostly applicable at the clinical level (Reference CarmanCarman et al., 2013), and its effective translation into routine practice will require a change in the status quo, which in turn will require greater investment in educating the public about health and health care, and the acquisition of skills and competencies to ask questions, express values and preferences, and understand risks. This transformation is necessary more than ever, at both the individual and system level, for ethical, financial, social, political and legal (in some countries) reasons. Finally, it forms a core element of health care quality, with more responsive services likely to lead to better outcomes, improved patient experiences and more effective self-management.

Conclusion

In summary, health care decisions that will lead to improved population health, patient experience and cost-effectiveness depend on an understanding of the best available scientific evidence and on patients’ informed values and preferences. SDM is an approach that has the potential to improve population health by reducing harms of treatments that are not beneficial for all and increasing the benefits of those that are. It also has the potential to improve patient experience by engaging them in the decision-making process. In addition, although the evidence remains patchy, it has the potential to ensure a more appropriate use of limited resources and thus increase the cost-effectiveness and sustainability of health systems. There are effective interventions for facilitating SDM, including training health care professionals and patient decision aids. However, SDM is not yet widely implemented in routine clinical practice, with various barriers obstructing its adoption at the individual patient and provider level and, more importantly perhaps, at organizational and system levels. These barriers can be overcome by establishing a culture of patient engagement at all levels of the health care system, from individual decisions and programme development to research and health policy.

Note

We would like to acknowledge Louisa Blair who edited the manuscript. Funding was provided by the Canada Research Chair in Shared Decision Making and Knowledge Translation.

References

1177 Vårdguiden (2016). Patient Act. Sweden: Skane. Available at: https://www.1177.se/Other-languages/Engelska/Regler-och-rattigheter/Patientlagen/ (accessed 27 September 2017).Google Scholar
Aboumatar, HJ, et al.(2013). The impact of health literacy on desire for participation in healthcare, medical visit communication, and patient reported outcomes among patients with hypertension. Journal of General Internal Medicine, 28:146976.Google Scholar
Adams, JR, et al.(2012). Communicating With Physicians About Medical Decisions: A Reluctance to Disagree. Archives of Internal Medicine, 172:11846.Google Scholar
Agency for Healthcare Research and Quality (2016). Developing Measures of Shared Decision Making (R01). Available at: https://grants.nih.gov/grants/guide/pa-files/PA-16–424.html (accessed 29 September 2017).Google Scholar
Al-Janabi, H, Flynn, TN, Coast, J (2012). Development of a self-report measure of capability wellbeing for adults: the ICECAP-A. Quality of Life Research, 21:16776.Google Scholar
Alden, DL, et al.(2014). Cultural targeting and tailoring of shared decision making technology: a theoretical framework for improving the effectiveness of patient decision aids in culturally diverse groups. Social Science & Medicine, 105:18.Google Scholar
Alston, C, et al.(2012). Communicating with patients on health care evidence. Washington, DC: Institute of Medicine of the National Academies.Google Scholar
Anell, A, Glenngård, A (2014). The use of outcome and process indicators to incentivize integrated care for frail older people: a case study of primary care services in Sweden. International Journal of Integrated Care, 14:e038.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Arimori, N (2006). Randomized controlled trial of decision aids for women considering prenatal testing: the effect of the Ottawa personal decision guide on decisional conflict. Japan Journal of Nursing Science, 3:11930.Google Scholar
Ballard-Barbash, R (2012). Multilevel intervention research applications in cancer care delivery. Journal of the National Cancer Institute Monograph, 44:1212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barr, PJ, Elwyn, G (2015). Measurement challenges in shared decision making: putting the ‘patient’ in patient-reported measures. Health Expectations, 19(5):9931001.Google Scholar
Barr, PJ, et al.(2014). The psychometric properties of CollaboRATE: a fast and frugal patient-reported measure of the shared decision-making process. Journal of Medical Internet Research, 16:e2.Google Scholar
Barr, PJ, et al.(2017). Evaluating CollaboRATE in a clinical setting: analysis of mode effects on scores, response rates and costs of data collection. BMJ Open, 7:e014681.Google Scholar
Belanger, E, Rodriguez, C, Groleau, D (2011). Shared decision-making in palliative care: a systematic mixed studies review using narrative synthesis. Palliative Medicine, 25:24261.Google Scholar
Blanc, X, et al.(2014). Publication trends of shared decision making in 15 high impact medical journals: a full-text review with bibliometric analysis. BMC Medical Informatics and Decision Making, 14:19.Google Scholar
Bouniols, N, Leclère, B, Moret, L (2016). Evaluating the quality of shared decision making during the patient-carer encounter: a systematic review of tools. BMC Research Notes, 9:382.Google Scholar
Bravo, P, et al.(2011). Shared decision making in Chile: supportive policies and research initiatives. Zeitschrift für Evidenz, Fortbildung und Qualität im Gesundheitswesen, 105:2548.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Brehaut, JC, et al.(2003). Validation of a decision regret scale. Medical Decision Making, 23:28192.Google Scholar
Buetow, S, Kenealy, T (2007). Ideological debates in family medicine. New York: Biomedical Books.Google Scholar
Bundesministerium für Gesundheit (2013). Gesetz zur Verbesserung der Rechte von Patientinnen und Patienten. Berlin, Germany: Bundesministerium für Gesundheit.Google Scholar
Caldon, LJ, et al.(2011). Clinicians’ concerns about decision support interventions for patients facing breast cancer surgery options: understanding the challenge of implementing shared decision-making. Health Expectations, 14:13346.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Carman, KL, et al.(2013). Patient and family engagement: a framework for understanding the elements and developing interventions and policies. Health Affairs (Millwood), 32:22331.Google Scholar
Charles, C, Gafni, A, Whelan, T (1997). Shared decision-making in the medical encounter: what does it mean? (or it takes at least two to tango). Social Science & Medicine, 44:68192.Google Scholar
Chewning, B, et al.(2012). Patient preferences for shared decisions: a systematic review. Patient Education and Counseling, 86:918.Google Scholar
Clayman, ML, et al.(2012). Development of a shared decision making coding system for analysis of patient-healthcare provider encounters. Patient Education and Counseling, 88:36772.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Coffey, M, et al.(2016). Study protocol: a mixed methods study to assess mental health recovery, shared decision-making and quality of life (Plan4Recovery). BMC Health Services Research, 16:392.Google Scholar
Coleman-Brueckheimer, K, Spitzer, J, Koffman, J (2009). Involvement of Rabbinic and communal authorities in decision-making by haredi Jews in the UK with breast cancer: an interpretative phenomenological analysis. Social Science & Medicine, 68:32333.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Conway, PH, Mostashari, F, Clancy, C (2013). The future of quality measurement for improvement and accountability. JAMA, 309:221516.Google Scholar
Couet, N, et al.(2015). Assessments of the extent to which healthcare providers involve patients in decision making: a systematic review of studies using the OPTION instrument. Health Expectations, 18:54261.Google Scholar
Coulter, A (2011). Making Shared Decision-Making a Reality. London: King’s Fund.Google Scholar
Coulter, A (2017). Shared decision making: everyone wants it, so why isn’t it happening? World Psychiatry, 16:11718.Google Scholar
Coulter, A, et al.(2015). European experience with shared decision making. International Journal of Person Centered Medicine, 5(1):6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coulter, A, et al.(2017). Shared decision making in the UK: moving towards wider uptake. Zeitschrift für Evidenz, Fortbildung und Qualität im Gesundheitswesen, 123:99103.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dahl Steffensen, K, Hjelholt Baker, V, Vinter, MM (2017). Implementing shared decision making in Denmark: first steps and future focus areas. Zeitschrift für Evidenz, Fortbildung und Qualität im Gesundheitswesen, 123:3640.Google Scholar
Decary, S, et al.(2017). Decisional conflict screening for a diversity of primary care decisions. Are we SURE yet? Journal of Clinical Epidemiology 89: 2389.Google Scholar
Degner, LF, Sloan, JA (1992). Decision making during serious illness: what role do patients really want to play? Journal of Clinical Epidemiology, 45:94150.Google Scholar
DeKeyser Ganz, F, et al.(2016). Development of a Model of Interprofessional Shared Clinical Decision Making in the ICU: a Mixed-Methods Study. Critical Care Medicine, 44:6809.Google Scholar
Desroches, S, et al.(2011). Exploring dietitians’ salient beliefs about shared decision-making behaviors. Implementation Science, 6:57.Google Scholar
Diouf, NT, et al.(2016). Training health professionals in shared decision making: update of an international environmental scan. Patient Education and Counseling, 99(11):17538.Google Scholar
Durand, MA, et al.(2014). Do interventions designed to support shared decision-making reduce health inequalities? A systematic review and meta-analysis. PLoS One, 9:e94670.Google Scholar
Durand, MA, et al.(2015). Can shared decision-making reduce medical malpractice litigation? A systematic review. BMC Health Services Research, 15:167.Google Scholar
Dy, SM (2007). Instruments for Evaluating Shared Medical Decision Making: a Structured Literature Review. Medical Care Research and Review, 64(6):62349.Google Scholar
Dy, SM, Purnell, TS (2012). Key concepts relevant to quality of complex and shared decision-making in health care: a literature review. Social Science & Medicine, 74:5827.Google Scholar
Effing, T, et al. (2007). Self-management education for patients with chronic obstructive pulmonary disease. Cochrane Database of Systematic Reviews, CD002990.Google Scholar
Elwyn, G, Frosch, DL, Kobrin, S (2016). Implementing shared decision-making: consider all the consequences. Implementation Science, 11:114.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Elwyn, G, Tilburt, J, Montori, V (2013). The ethical imperative for shared decision-making. European Journal for Person Centered Healthcare, 14:12931.Google Scholar
Elwyn, G, et al.(2000). Shared decision making and the concept of equipoise: the competences of involving patients in healthcare choices. British Journal of General Practice, 50:8929.Google ScholarPubMed
Elwyn, G, et al.(2001). Measuring the involvement of patients in shared decision-making: a systematic review of instruments. Patient Education and Counseling, 43:522.Google Scholar
Elwyn, G, et al.(2005). Shared decision making measurement using the OPTION instrument. Cardiff: Cardiff University. Available at: http://www.glynelwyn.com/uploads/2/4/0/4/24040341/option_12_book.pdf (accessed 28 June 2018).Google Scholar
Elwyn, G, et al.(2012). Shared decision making: a model for clinical practice. Journal of General Internal Medicine, 27:13617.Google Scholar
Elwyn, G, et al.(2013). “Many miles to go …”: a systematic review of the implementation of patient decision support interventions into routine clinical practice. BMC Medical Informatics and Decision Making, 13.Google Scholar
Specialisten, Federatie Medisch (2015). Onderwerp: Samen beslissen. Utrecht, Netherlands. Available at: http://www.demedischspecialist.nl/samen-beslissen (accessed 29 September 2016).Google Scholar
Fisher, B, et al.(2002). Twenty-year follow-up of a randomized trial comparing total mastectomy, lumpectomy, and lumpectomy plus irradiation for the treatment of invasive breast cancer. New England Journal of Medicine, 347:123341.Google Scholar
Frosch, DL, Carman, KL (2016). Embracing patient and family engagement to advance shared decision making. In: Elwyn, G, Edwards, A, Thompson, R (eds). Shared Decision Making in Health Care: Achieving evidence-based patient choice. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1318.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frosch, DL, et al.(2009). Adjuncts or adversaries to shared decision-making? Applying the Integrative Model of behavior to the role and design of decision support interventions in healthcare interactions. Implementation Science, 4:73.Google Scholar
Frosch, DL, et al.(2012). Authoritarian physicians and patients’ fear of being labeled ‘difficult’ among key obstacles to shared decision making. Health Affairs, 31:1030.Google Scholar
Garvelink, MM, et al.(2016). Development of a decision guide to support the elderly in decision making about location of care: an iterative, user-centered design. Research Involvement and Engagement, 2:116.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Geiger, F, Kasper, J (2012). Of blind men and elephants: suggesting SDM-MASS as a compound measure for shared decision making integrating patient, physician and observer views. Zeitschrift für Evidenz, Fortbildung und Qualität im Gesundheitswesen, 106:2849.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gibson, A, Britten, N, Lynch, J (2012). Theoretical directions for an emancipatory concept of patient and public involvement. Health, 16:53147.Google Scholar
Godolphin, W, Towle, A, McKendry, R (2001). Challenges in family practice related to informed and shared decision-making: a survey of preceptors of medical students. JAMC, 165:4345.Google Scholar
Government of the United Kingdom (2012). Health and Social Care Act 2012, c.7.Google Scholar
Hagbaghery, MA, Salsali, M, Ahmadi, F (2004). The factors facilitating and inhibiting effective clinical decision-making in nursing: a qualitative study. BMC Nursing, 3:111.Google Scholar
Hamilton, JG, et al.(2017). What is a good medical decision? A research agenda guided by perspectives from multiple stakeholders. Journal of Behavioral Medicine, 40(1):5268.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hanson, LC, et al.(2011). Improving Decision-Making for Feeding Options in Advanced Dementia: a Randomized, Controlled Trial. Journal of the American Geriatrics Society, 59:200916.Google Scholar
Härter, M, van der Weijden, T, Elwyn, G (2011). Policy and practice developments in the implementation of shared decision making: an international perspective. Zeitschrift für Evidenz, Fortbildung und Qualität im Gesundheitswesen, 105:22933.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Härter, M, et al.(2017a). The long way of implementing patient-centered care and shared decision making in Germany. Zeitschrift für Evidenz, Fortbildung und Qualität im Gesundheitswesen, 123:4651.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Härter, M, et al.(2017b). Shared decision making in 2017: international accomplishments in policy, research and implementation. Zeitschrift für Evidenz, Fortbildung und Qualität im Gesundheitswesen, 123:15.Google Scholar
Hawley, ST, Morris, AM (2017). Cultural challenges to engaging patients in shared decision making. Patient Education and Counseling, 100(1):1824.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Illich, I (1975). Limits to Medicine: Medical Nemesis: the Expropriation of Health. London: Marion Boyards Publishers Ltd.Google Scholar
Joseph-Williams, N, Edwards, A, Elwyn, G (2014). Power imbalance prevents shared decision making. BMJ, 348:g3178.Google Scholar
Kasper, J, et al.(2012). MAPPIN’ SDM–the multifocal approach to sharing in shared decision making. PLoS One, 7:e34849.Google Scholar
Katz, SJ, Kurian, AW, Morrow, M (2015). Treatment decision making and genetic testing for breast cancer: mainstreaming mutations. JAMA, 314:9978.Google Scholar
Kelders, SM, et al.(2016). Health Behavior Change Support Systems as a research discipline. A viewpoint. International Journal of Medical Informatics, 93:310.Google Scholar
Kiesler, DJ, Auerbach, SM (2006). Optimal matches of patient preferences for information, decision-making and interpersonal behavior: evidence, models and interventions. Patient Education and Counseling, 61:31941.Google Scholar
King, JS, Moulton, BW (2006). Rethinking informed consent: the case for shared medical decision-making. American Journal of Law & Medicine, 32:429501.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kirwan, JR, et al.(2016). Commentary: Patients as Partners. Building on the Experience of Outcome Measures in Rheumatology. Arthritis & Rheumatology, 68:13346.Google Scholar
Korda, H, Eldridge, GN (2011). Payment incentives and integrated care delivery: levers for health system reform and cost containment. Inquiry, 48:27787.Google Scholar
Koster, J (2016). Pubmed PubReMiner. 1.14 ed. Amsterdam: Department of Oncogenomics, AMC.Google Scholar
Kraetschmer, N, et al.(2004). How does trust affect patient preferences for participation in decision-making? Health Expectations, 7:31726.Google Scholar
Kriston, L, et al.(2010). The 9-item Shared Decision Making Questionnaire (SDM-Q-9). Development and psychometric properties in a primary care sample. Patient Education and Counseling, 80:949.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kronick, R, Casalino, LP, Bindman, AB (2015). Apple pickers or federal judges: strong versus weak incentives in physician payment. Health Services Research, 50:204956.Google Scholar
Krupat, E, et al.(2001). When physicians and patients think alike: patient-centered beliefs and their impact on satisfaction and trust. Journal of Family Practice, 50:105762.Google Scholar
Kryworuchko, J, et al.(2008). Appraisal of primary outcome measures used in trials of patient decision support. Patient Education and Counseling, 73:497503.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kunneman, M, Montori, VM (2016). When patient-centred care is worth doing well: informed consent or shared decision-making. BMJ Quality & Safety, 26(7):5224.Google Scholar
Laidsaar-Powell, RC, et al.(2013). Physician–patient–companion communication and decision-making: a systematic review of triadic medical consultations. Patient Education and Counseling, 91:313.Google Scholar
Leape, LL (1989). Unnecessary surgery. Health Services Research, 24:351407.Google Scholar
LeBlanc, A, et al.(2009). Decisional conflict in patients and their physicians: a dyadic approach to shared decision making. Medical Decision Making, 29:618.Google Scholar
Lee, YK, Low, WY, Ng, CJ (2013). Exploring patient values in medical decision making: a qualitative study. PLoS One, 8:e80051.Google Scholar
Légaré, F, Witteman, HO (2013). Interventions for increasing the use of shared decision making by healthcare professionals. Health Affairs (Millwood), 32:27684.Google Scholar
Légaré, F, Stacey, D, Pouliot, S (2011). Interprofessionalism and shared decision-making in primary care: a stepwise approach towards a new model. Journal of Interprofessional Care, 25.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Légaré, F, et al.(2006). Primary health care professionals’ views on barriers and facilitators to the implementation of the Ottawa Decision Support Framework in practice. Patient Education and Counseling, 63:38090.Google Scholar
Légaré, F, et al.(2007). Instruments to assess the perception of physicians in the decision-making process of specific clinical encounters: a systematic review. BMC Medical Informatics and Decision Making, 7:30.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Légaré, F, et al.(2008). Barriers and facilitators to implementing shared decision-making in clinical practice: update of a systematic review of health professionals’ perceptions. Patient Education and Counseling, 73:52635.Google Scholar
Légaré, F, et al.(2010). Are you SURE?: assessing patient decisional conflict with a 4-item screening test. Canadian Family Physician, 56:e30814.Google Scholar
Légaré, F, et al.(2012a). Some but not all dyadic measures in shared decision making research have satisfactory psychometric properties. Journal of Clinical Epidemiology, 65:131020.Google Scholar
Légaré, F, et al.(2012b). Patients’ Perceptions of Sharing in Decisions. Patient, 5:119.Google Scholar
Légaré, F, et al.(2013). Core competencies for shared decision making training programs: insights from an international, interdisciplinary working group. Journal of Continuing Education in the Health Professions, 33:26773.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Légaré, F, et al. (2014). Interventions for improving the adoption of shared decision making by healthcare professionals. Cochrane Database of Systematic Reviews, CD006732.Google Scholar
Légaré, F, et al.(2015). Improving Decision making On Location of Care with the frail Elderly and their caregivers (the DOLCE study): study protocol for a cluster randomized controlled trial. Trials, 16:50.Google Scholar
Lepine, J, et al.(2016). What factors influence health professionals to use decision aids for Down syndrome prenatal screening? BMC Pregnancy and Childbirth, 16:262.Google Scholar
Levy, SM, et al.(1989). Breast conservation versus mastectomy: distress sequelae as a function of choice. Journal of Clinical Oncology: 7:367.Google Scholar
Makoul, G, Clayman, ML (2006). An integrative model of shared decision making in medical encounters. Patient Education and Counseling, 60:30112.Google Scholar
Makoul, G, Arntson, P, Schofield, T (1995). Health promotion in primary care: physician–patient communication and decision making about prescription medications. Social Science & Medicine, 41:124154.Google Scholar
Mannion, R, Braithwaite, J (2012). Unintended consequences of performance measurement in healthcare: 20 salutary lessons from the English National Health Service. Internal Medicine Journal, 42:569.Google Scholar
Mead, EL, et al.(2013). Shared decision-making for cancer care among racial and ethnic minorities: a systematic review. American Journal of Public Health, 103:e1529.Google Scholar
Melbourne, E, et al.(2011). Dyadic OPTION: measuring perceptions of shared decision-making in practice. Patient Education and Counseling, 83:557.Google Scholar
Menzel, H, Coleman, J, Katz, E (1959). Dimensions of being “Modern” in medical practice. Journal of Chronic Diseases, 9:2040.Google Scholar
Morgan, DJ, et al.(2016). 2016 Update on Medical Overuse: a systematic review. JAMA Internal Medicine, 176(11):168792.Google Scholar
Moulton, B, et al.(2013). From informed consent to informed request: do we need a new gold standard? Journal of the Royal Society of Medicine, 106:3914.Google Scholar
Moumjid, N, et al.(2017). Moving towards shared decision making in the physician–patient encounter in France: state of the art and future prospects. Zeitschrift für Evidenz, Fortbildung und Qualität im Gesundheitswesen, 123:415.Google Scholar
Mulley, AG, Trimble, C, Elwyn, G (2012). Stop the silent misdiagnosis: patients’ preferences matter. BMJ, 345:e6572.Google Scholar
National Institute for Health and Care Excellence (2016). Shared Decision Making Collaborative – An Action Plan. Available at: https://www.nice.org.uk/Media/Default/About/what-we-do/shared-decision-making-collaborative-action-plan.pdf (accessed 28 June 2018).Google Scholar
England, NHS (n/d). Shared Decision Making. Available at: https://www .england.nhs.uk/shared-decision-making/ (accessed 28 June 2018).Google Scholar
Rightcare, NHS (2017). Evidence Search. London: National Institute for Health and Care Excellence.Google Scholar
Nolte, E, Knai, C, Saltman, RB (eds) (2014). Assessing chronic disease management in European health systems. Copenhagen: WHO Regional Office for Europe on behalf of the European Observatory on Health Systems and Policies.Google Scholar
O’Connor, AM (1995). Validation of a decisional conflict scale. Medical Decision Making, 15:2530.Google Scholar
OECD (2015). Doctors’ consultations. Available at: https://data.oecd.org/healthcare/doctors-consultations.htm (accessed 16 August 2017).Google Scholar
Ottawa Hospital Research Institute (2015). Patient Decision Aids. Ottawa, Canada: Ottawa Hospital Research Institute. Available at: decisionaid.ohri.ca/index.html (accessed 28 June 2018).Google Scholar
Pauker, SG, Kassirer, JP (1997). Contentious screening decisions: does the choice matter? New England Journal of Medicine, 336:12434.Google Scholar
Porter, ME (2010). What Is Value in Health Care? New England Journal of Medicine, 363:247781.Google Scholar
President’s Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research (1982). Making Health Care Decisions. The Ethical and Legal Implications of Informed Consent in the Patient–Practitioner Relationship. Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office.Google Scholar
Rahimi, SA, Alizadeh, M, Légaré, F (2017). Shared decision making in Iran: Current and future trends. Zeitschrift für Evidenz, Fortbildung und Qualität im Gesundheitswesen, 123:525.Google Scholar
Rapley, T (2008). Distributed decision making: the anatomy of decisions-in-action. Sociology of Health & Illness, 30:42944.Google Scholar
Rapley, T, et al.(2006). Doctor–patient interaction in a randomised controlled trial of decision-support tools. Social Science & Medicine, 62:226778.Google Scholar
Française, République (2002). Loi n 2002–303 du 4 mars 2002 relative aux droits des malades et à la qualité du système de santé. Available at: https://www.legifrance.gouv.fr/affichTexte.do?cidTexte=JORFTEXT000000227015 (accessed 28 June 2018).Google Scholar
Rijksoverheid (2015). Kamerbrief over Samen beslissen. Available at: https://www.rijksoverheid.nl/documenten/kamerstukken/2015/10/29/kamerbrief-over-samen-beslissen (accessed 29 September 2016).Google Scholar
Ringard, A, et al.(2013). Norway: health system review. Health Systems in Transition, 15:1162.Google Scholar
Rodenburg-Vandenbussche, S, et al.(2015). Dutch Translation and Psychometric Testing of the 9-Item Shared Decision Making Questionnaire (SDM-Q-9) and Shared Decision Making Questionnaire-Physician Version (SDM-Q-Doc) in Primary and Secondary Care. PLoS One, 10:e0132158.Google Scholar
Saarimaki, ASD (2013). Are you using effective tools to support patients facing tough cancer-related decisions? Canadian Oncology Nursing Journal, 23:13744.Google Scholar
Seminar, Salzburg Global (2011). Salzburg statement on shared decision making. BMJ, 342:d1745.Google Scholar
Sandman, L, Gustavsson, E, Munthe, C (2016). Individual responsibility as ground for priority setting in shared decision-making. Journal of Medical Ethics, 42(10):6538.Google Scholar
Schattner, A (2002). What do patients really want to know? QJM, 95:1356.Google Scholar
Scholl, I, et al.(2011). Measurement of shared decision making – a review of instruments. Zeitschrift für Evidenz, Fortbildung und Qualität im Gesundheitswesen, 105:31324.Google Scholar
Scholl, I, et al.(2012). Development and psychometric properties of the Shared Decision Making Questionnaire – physician version (SDM-Q-Doc). Patient Education and Counseling, 88:28490.Google Scholar
Selby, K, Auer, R, Cornuz, J (2017). Shared decision making in preventive care in Switzerland: from theory to action. Zeitschrift für Evidenz, Fortbildung und Qualität im Gesundheitswesen, 123:914.Google Scholar
Sepucha, K, Mulley AG jr (2009). A perspective on the patient’s role in treatment decisions. Medical Care Research and Review, 66:53S74S.Google Scholar
Sepucha, KR, Scholl, I (2014). Measuring shared decision making: a review of constructs, measures, and opportunities for cardiovascular care. Circulation: Cardiovascular Quality and Outcomes, 7:6206.Google Scholar
Sepucha, KR, Fowler FJ jr, Mulley AG jr (2004). Policy support for patient-centered care: the need for measurable improvements in decision quality. Health Affairs (Millwood), Suppl Variation, VAR5462.Google Scholar
Sewitch, MJ, et al.(2003). Patient nonadherence to medication in inflammatory bowel disease. American Journal of Gastroenterology, 98:153544.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Shay, LA, Lafata, JE (2014). Understanding patient perceptions of shared decision making. Patient Education and Counseling, 96:295301.Google Scholar
Shay, LA, Lafata, JE (2015). Where is the Evidence? A Systematic Review of Shared Decision Making and Patient Outcomes. Medical Decision Making, 35:11431.Google Scholar
Simon, D, Loh, A, Harter, M (2007). Measuring (shared) decision-making – a review of psychometric instruments. Zeitschrift fur arztliche Fortbildung und Qualitatssicherung, 101:25967.Google Scholar
Sniehotta, F (2009). An Experimental Test of the Theory of Planned Behavior. Applied Psychology: Health and Well-Being, 1:25770.Google Scholar
Sorbero, ME, et al.(2008). Outcome Measures for Effective Teamwork in Inpatient Care. Final Report. Santa Monica: RAND Corporation.Google Scholar
Spatz, ES, Krumholz, HM, Moulton, BW (2016). The new era of informed consent: getting to a reasonable-patient standard through shared decision making. JAMA, 315:20634.Google Scholar
Stacey, D, et al.(2010). Shared decision making models to inform an interprofessional perspective on decision making: a theory analysis. Patient Education and Counseling, 80:16472.Google Scholar
Stacey, D, et al.(2013). Coaching and guidance with patient decision aids: a review of theoretical and empirical evidence. BMC Medical Informatics and Decision Making, 13:S11.Google Scholar
Stacey, D, et al.(2017). Decision aids for people facing health treatment or screening decisions. Cochrane Database of Systematic Reviews, 4, CD001431.Google Scholar
Stalmeier, P (2012). Med-Decs International Database for Support on Medical Choices. Available at: http://www.med-decs.org/en (accessed 28 June 2018).Google Scholar
Starfield, B, et al.(1979). Patient-doctor agreement about problems needing follow-up visit. JAMA, 242:3446.Google Scholar
Stewart, M (2001). Towards a global definition of patient centred care. BMJ, 322:4445.Google Scholar
Stewart, M (2003). Patient-centered medicine: transforming the clinical method. Abingdon: Radcliffe Med Press.Google Scholar
Stiggelbout, AM, Pieterse, AH, De Haes, JC (2015). Shared decision making: concepts, evidence, and practice. Patient Education and Counseling, 98:11729.Google Scholar
Street, RL, et al.(2009). How does communication heal? Pathways linking clinician–patient communication to health outcomes. Patient Education and Counseling, 74:295301.Google Scholar
Thompson, AG (2007). The meaning of patient involvement and participation in health care consultations: a taxonomy. Social Science & Medicine, 64:1297310.Google Scholar
Thomson, R, Murtagh, M, Khaw, F (2005). Tensions in public health policy: patient engagement, evidence-based public health and health inequalities. Quality & Safety in Health Care, 14:398400.Google Scholar
Tobias, JS, Souhami, RL (1993). Fully informed consent can be needlessly cruel. BMJ, 307:1199201.Google Scholar
Tragakes, E, et al.(2008). Latvia: health system review. Health systems in transition, 10(2): 1253.Google Scholar
Trenaman, L, Bryan, S, Bansback, N (2014). The cost-effectiveness of patient decision aids: a systematic review. Healthcare (Amsterdam), 2:2517.Google Scholar
Tudiver, F, et al.(2002). What influences family physicians’ cancer screening decisions when practice guidelines are unclear or conflicting? Journal of Family Practice, 51:760.Google Scholar
Ubbink, DT, Santema, TB, Lapid, O (2016). Shared Decision-Making in Cosmetic Medicine and Aesthetic Surgery. Aesthetic Surgery Journal, 36:NP14NP19.Google Scholar
US Congress (2010). Patient Protection and Affordable Care Act. Library of Congress.Google Scholar
van der Weijden, T, et al.(2017). Shared decision making, a buzz-word in the Netherlands, the pace quickens towards nationwide implementation. Zeitschrift für Evidenz, Fortbildung und Qualität im Gesundheitswesen, 123:6974.Google Scholar
Veatch, R (1972). Models for Ethical Medicine in a Revolutionary Age. Hastings Center Report, 2:57.Google Scholar
Volk, RJ, et al.(2013). Ten years of the International Patient Decision Aid Standards Collaboration: evolution of the core dimensions for assessing the quality of patient decision aids. BMC Medical Informatics and Decision Making, 13 Suppl 2:S1.Google Scholar
Volk, RJ, et al.(2016). Patient Decision Aids for Colorectal Cancer Screening: A Systematic Review and Meta-analysis. American Journal of Preventive Medicine, 51(5):77991.Google Scholar
Walsh, T, et al.(2014). Undetermined impact of patient decision support interventions on healthcare costs and savings: a systematic review. BMJ, 348:g188.Google Scholar
Washington State Health Care Authority (2016). Engaging health consumers through Shared Decision Making (SDM). Washington: Washington State Health Care Authority.Google Scholar
Weinstein, JN (2000). The missing piece: embracing shared decision making to reform health care. Spine, 25:14.Google Scholar
Weinstein, JN, Clay, K, Morgan, TS (2007). Informed patient choice: patient-centered valuing of surgical risks and benefits. Health Affairs (Millwood), 26:72630.Google Scholar
Weiss, MC, et al.(2015). Medication decision making and patient outcomes in GP, nurse and pharmacist prescriber consultations. Primary Health Care Research & Development, 16:51327.Google Scholar
Wennberg, J, Gittelsohn (1973). Small area variations in health care delivery. Science, 182:11028.Google Scholar
West, AF, West, RR (2002). Clinical decision-making: coping with uncertainty. Postgraduate Medical Journal, 78:31921.Google Scholar
Weston, WW (2001). Informed and shared decision-making: the crux of patient-centered care. CMAJ, 165:4389.Google Scholar
Woolf, SH (2001). Editorial: the Logic and Limits of Shared Decision Making. Journal of Urology, 166:244245.Google Scholar
Organization, World Health (2017). Case Studies on Enforcement of Tobacco Control Legislation. Available at: http://www.who.int/tobacco/research/legislation/case_studies_index/en/ (accessed 29 September 2017).Google Scholar
Zikmund-Fisher, BJ, et al.(2016). Perceived Barriers to Implementing Individual Choosing Wisely(R) Recommendations in Two National Surveys of Primary Care Providers. Journal of General Internal Medicine, 32(2): 21017.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×