from II - Key Themes
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 29 April 2023
In considering the place and importance of definitions in ancient logic,1 the most appropriate point of departure is Aristotle’s commendation at Metaphysics 1.6, 987b1–3 of the historical Socrates (as opposed to the character portrayed in the Platonic dialogues) for being the first to focus attention on definitions in the course of his ethical inquiries, an unmistakable reference to early ‘definitional’ dialogues such as the Euthyphro, Laches, Charmides, and Meno.2 None of these works contains any occurrences of Aristotle’s term for definition, horismos, or its close relative, horos,3 but this does not automatically undermine Aristotle’s ascription. In the ethical inquiries represented in these dialogues Socrates typically begins by identifying someone who is reputed to possess expertise concerning one or another of the ethical virtues (viz. temperance, courage, justice, or piety), and then insists that anyone who really possessed such expertise should be able to say what is the object of her alleged expertise. Consequently, Socrates demands that his interlocutors produce defensible answers to questions of the form, ‘What is X?’, (ti esti X;) where appropriate substituends of ‘X’ are names of the individual virtues. For example, when the title character of the Euthyphro informs Socrates that he is prosecuting his own father for murder on a highly dubious factual basis, Socrates declares that to undertake this prosecution Euthyphro must have ‘precise’ (akribōs) knowledge of piety and impiety, and in that case he should be able to answer the questions ‘What is piety?’ and ‘What is impiety?’ (Euthyphro 4e–5d). Inasmuch as this form of question can plausibly be construed as a demand to be told what distinguishes X things from everything else, or in other words, to be given a definition of X, if we assume that Plato’s portrayal of Socrates in these texts is accurate, then they seem to support Aristotle’s historical contention that Socrates sought definitions of the virtues as part of his ethical research program.
To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.