Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-mlc7c Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-19T09:31:25.507Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Memory

from ENTRIES

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2016

John Sutton
Affiliation:
University of Macquarie
Lawrence Nolan
Affiliation:
California State University, Long Beach
Get access

Summary

Descartes thought about memory in the distinct contexts of method, metaphysics, medicine, mortality, and morals. Keenly aware of the fallibility and instability of natural corporeal memory, he considered various ways to bypass it or avoid relying on it, but he also came to see its importance in understanding and dealing with the passions and the union of mind and body (see human being). His account of memory influenced Malebranche and associationist traditions but was subject to sharp attack from critics who saw it as dangerously materialist and chaotic.

In the Rules, Descartes worries that the intellect must rely on memory to connect the steps in a reasoning process. But “since memory is weak and unstable, it must be refreshed and strengthened” by a continuous and repeated “movement of thought,” until the thinker can intuit the whole series of operations, passing over them all “so quickly that memory is left with practically no role to play” (AT X 409, CSM I 38) (see deduction). Descartes was not attracted to artificial memory techniques, turning instead to anatomy and physiology to “explain what imagination, memory, etc. consist in” (AT I 263, CSMK 40). In the Treatise on Man, Descartes writes that “the effect of memory that seems to me to be most worthy of consideration here is that, without there being any soul present in this machine, it can naturally be disposed to imitate all the movements” of real humans (AT XI 15, G 157). So there is genuine memory in soul-less bodies: Descartes is consistent in attributing memory to animals (AT IV 310, CSMK 270).

Corporeal ideas are figures traced by animal spirits on the surface of the pineal gland. These occurrent impressions then leave traces “on the internal part of the brain … which is the seat of memory” (AT XI 176–77, CSM I 106; H 86–87; G 149–50). Flowing through the gaps between the tiny fibers of the brain, the spirits enlarge or alter these pores, continually bending and rearranging the fibers and tubes. When the movement of the spirits is stronger, long-lasting, or often repeated, these patterns “are retained there in such a way that by means of them the ideas that existed previously on this gland can be formed again long afterward, without requiring the presence of the objects to which they correspond.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Descartes, René. 1998. The World and Other Writings, trans. and ed. Gaukroger, S.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Descartes, René. 1996. Le monde, l'homme, ed. (with notes) Bitbol-Hespériès, A. and Verdet, J.-P.. Paris: Éditions du Seuil.Google Scholar
Descartes, René. 1972. Treatise of Man: René Descartes, trans. and ed. Hall, T. S.. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Draaisma, Douwe. 2000. Metaphors of Memory.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Fóti, Véronique M. 2000. “Descartes’ Intellectual and Corporeal Memories,” in Descartes’ Natural Philosophy, ed. Gaukroger, S., Schuster, J., and Sutton, J.. London: Routledge, 591–603.Google Scholar
Glanvill, Joseph. 1661. The Vanity of Dogmatizing.London: Henry Eversden.Google Scholar
Hatfield, Gary. 2007. “The Passions of the Soul and Descartes's Machine Physiology,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 38: 1–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Joyce, Richard. 1997. “Cartesian Memory,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 35: 375–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kieft, Xavier. 2006. “Mémoire corporelle, mémoire intellectuelle et unite de l'individu selon Descartes,” Revue Philosophique de Louvain 104: 762–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krell, David F. 1990. Of Memory, Reminiscence, and Writing: On the Verge.Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Landormy, Paul. 1902. “La mémoire corporelle et la mémoire intellectuelle dans la philosophie de Descartes,” Bibliothèque du Congrès Internationale de Philosophie 4: 259–98.Google Scholar
MacIntosh, J. J. 1983. “Perception and Imagination in Descartes, Boyle, and Hooke,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 13: 327–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morris, John. 1969. “Pattern Recognition in Descartes’ Automata,” Isis 60: 451–60.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Reiss, Timothy. 1996. “Denying the Body? Memory and the Dilemmas of History in Descartes,” Journal of the History of Ideas 57: 587–607 (revised version in T. Reiss, Against Autonomy. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2002, 184–218).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sepper, Dennis. 1993. “Ingenium, Memory Art, and the Unity of Imaginative Knowing in the Early Descartes,” in Essays on the Philosophy and Science of René Descartes, ed. Voss, S.. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 142–61.Google Scholar
Sutton, John. 2000. “The Body and the Brain,” in Descartes’ Natural Philosophy, ed. Gaukroger, S., Schuster, J., and Sutton, J.. London: Routledge, 697–722.Google Scholar
Sutton, John. 1998. Philosophy and Memory Traces: Descartes to Connectionism.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Memory
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.170
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Memory
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.170
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Memory
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.170
Available formats
×