Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-pfhbr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-10T09:29:24.601Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

12 - Wrestling with biological complexity: from Darwin to Dawkins

from Part IV - Philosophical perspectives

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 July 2013

Charles H. Lineweaver
Affiliation:
Australian National University, Canberra
Paul C. W. Davies
Affiliation:
Arizona State University
Michael Ruse
Affiliation:
Florida State University
Get access

Summary

The inhabitants of each successive period in the world's history have beaten their predecessors in the race for life, and are, in so far, higher in the scale of nature; and this may account for that vague yet ill-defined sentiment, felt by many palæontologists, that organisation on the whole has progressed.

(Darwin, 1859, 345)

I have long been rather dubious about the notion of complexity. Certainly, it is not something that is always desirable. For instance, in theology, as is well known, a central Christian claim is that God is the ultimate simple. In mathematics, simplicity and elegance are highly valued. One thinks for example of the Euler identity: e + 1 = 0. And in science too, there is much to be said for simplicity. Charles Darwin's supporter Thomas Henry Huxley, on being informed about natural selection, is supposed to have exclaimed: “How simple, how stupid not to have thought of that!” More generally in science, the ultimate in scientific achievement is bringing disparate parts of enquiry together under the same hypothesis. This process, known as a “consilience of inductions”, is the paradigmatic exercise in producing simplicity (Whewell, 1840).

However, there is no doubt that the notion of complexity (and related notions of progress) continue to fascinate and absorb our attention. In this discussion, I would like to offer a few remarks about complexity (and progress) as they play out in evolutionary biology. To anticipate, it has long been recognized by historians of evolutionary biology that in the middle of the nineteenth century in Britain there were two competing views of the evolutionary process (Richards, 1987; Ruse, 2013a). One was expressed by Charles Darwin in his Origin of Species (1859), the other by Herbert Spencer in a series of writings, culminating in the 1860s with his First Principles (1862) and his Principles of Biology (1864).

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2013

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Barrett, P. H., Gautrey, P. J., Herbert, S., Kohn, D., & Smith, S. (eds.) (1987). Charles Darwin's Notebooks, 1836–1844. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Darwin, C. (1859). On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life. London: John Murray.Google Scholar
Darwin, C. (1861). Origin of Species (Third Edition). London: John Murray.Google Scholar
Darwin, C. (1985). The Correspondence of Charles Darwin. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dawkins, R. (1986). The Blind Watchmaker. New York, NY: Norton.Google Scholar
Dawkins, R. (1989). The evolution of evolvability. In Langton, C. G. (ed.), Artificial Life. 201–20. Redwood City, CA.: Addison-Wesley.Google Scholar
Dawkins, R. (1992). Progress. In Keller, E. F. & Lloyd, E. (eds.), Keywords in Evolutionary Biology. 263–272. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Dawkins, R. (1997). Human chauvinism: review of Full House by Stephen Jay Gould. Evolution 51, 3, 1015–1020.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dawkins, R. (2003). A Devil's Chaplain: Reflections on Hope, Lies, Science and Love. Boston and New York: Houghton Mifflin.Google Scholar
Dawkins, R. & Krebs, J. R. (1979). Arms races between and within species. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, B, 205, 489–511.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fisher, R. A. (1930). The Genetical Theory of Natural Selection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ford, E. B. (1931). Mendelism and Evolution. London: Methuen.Google Scholar
Goodwin, B. (2001). How the Leopard Changed its Spots, Second Edition. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Gould, S. J. (1996). Full House: the Spread of Excellence from Plato to Darwin. New York, NY: Paragon.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gray, J. L. (1894). Letters of Asa Gray. Boston: Houghton, Mifflin.Google Scholar
Gregory, T. R. (2001). Coincidence, coevolution, or causation? DNA content, cell size, and the C-value enigma. Biological Reviews, 76, 65–101.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Huxley, J. S. (1912). The Individual in the Animal Kingdom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Jerison, H. (1973). Evolution of the Brain and Intelligence. New York, NY: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Kauffman, S. A. (1995). At Home in the Universe: the Search for the Laws of Self-Organization and Complexity. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McShea, D. & Brandon, R. (2010). Biology's First Law: the Tendency for Diversity and Complexity to Increase in Evolutionary Systems. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maynard Smith, J. & Szathmary, E. (1995). The Major Transitions in Evolution. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Provine, W. B. (1971). The Origins of Theoretical Population Genetics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Provine, W. B. (1986). Sewall Wright and Evolutionary Biology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Richards, R. J. (1987). Darwin and the Emergence of Evolutionary Theories of Mind and Behavior. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Ruse, M. (1980). Charles Darwin and group selection. Annals of Science, 37, 615–630.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruse, M. (1996). Monad to Man: the Concept of Progress in Evolutionary Biology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Ruse, M. (1999). The Darwinian Revolution: Science Red in Tooth and Claw. Second edn. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Ruse, M. (2004). Adaptive landscapes and dynamic equilibrium: the Spencerian contribution to twentieth-century American evolutionary biology. In Lustig, A., Richards, R. J., & Ruse, M. (eds.), Darwinian Heresies, 131–50. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruse, M. (2006). Darwinism and its Discontents. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ruse, M. (2013a). The Cambridge Encyclopedia of Darwin and Evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ruse, M. (2013b). Gaia in Context: Plato to Pagans. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Spencer, H. (1852). A theory of population, deduced from the general law of animal fertility. Westminster Review, 1, 468–501.Google Scholar
Spencer, H. (1857). Progress: its law and cause. Westminster Review, LXVII, 244–267.Google Scholar
Spencer, H. (1862). First Principles. London: Williams and Norgate.Google Scholar
Spencer, H. 1864. Principles of Biology. London: Williams and Norgate.Google Scholar
Thompson, D. W. (1917). On Growth and Form. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whewell, W. (1840). The Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences. London: Parker.Google Scholar
Wright, S. (1931). Evolution in Mendelian populations. Genetics, 16, 97–159.Google ScholarPubMed
Wright, S. (1932). The roles of mutation, inbreeding, crossbreeding and selection in evolution. Proceedings of the Sixth International Congress of Genetics, 1, 356–66.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×