Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gxg78 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-19T15:40:15.998Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

III - The Mystification of Common-Law Reasoning

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

Larry Alexander
Affiliation:
University of San Diego School of Law
Emily Sherwin
Affiliation:
Cornell University Law School, New York
Get access

Summary

We argued in the preceding chapter that there are two and only two plausible models of judicial reasoning: the natural model and the rule model. The natural model incorporates two forms of reasoning: moral reasoning through the method of reflective equilibrium and empirical reasoning. The rule model adds a third form of reasoning, deduction from authoritative rules. These forms of reasoning are not unique to law but are common to all subjects of human deliberation. In our view, they are the only tools judges need to decide cases and the only tools they use in fact.

This is not the prevailing view. Texts on judicial reasoning, as well as judges themselves, often maintain that the primary decision-making method of the common law is reasoning by analogy. Analogical reasoning is the special art of lawyers and judges and the means by which the common law has successfully adapted to changing social conditions. Commentators also maintain that courts reason from legal principles, a method closely linked to the method of analogy.

In this chapter, we intend to demonstrate that judges cannot be doing what they claim. One cannot “reason” by analogy, and legal principles are chimerical. We argue as well that if analogies and legal principles could in fact operate as elements in judicial reasoning, they would tend to lead judges into error, without the compensating benefits of settlement.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2008

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Weinreb, Lloyd L., Legal Reason: The Use of Analogy in Legal Argument (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2005)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levi, Edward H., An Introduction to Legal Reasoning 1–6 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press 1948)Google Scholar
Sunstein, Cass R., Legal Reasoning and Political Conflict 62–100 (New York: Oxford University Press 1996)Google Scholar
Burton, Steven J., An Introduction to Law and Legal Reasoning 25–41 (Boston: Little, Brown 1995)Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph, The Authority of Law 183–89, 201–6 (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1979)Google Scholar
Lamond, Grant, Do Precedents Create Rules?, 11 Legal Theory 1 (2005)Google Scholar
Horty, John F., The Result Model of Precedent, 10 Legal Theory 19 (2004)Google Scholar
Brewer, Scott, Exemplary Reasoning: Semantics, Pragmatics, and the Rational Force of Legal Argument by Analogy, 109 Harv. L. Rev. 925, 925–29, 962–63 (1996)Google Scholar
Llewellyn, Karl N., The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals 77–87 (Boston: Little, Brown 1960)Google Scholar
Llewellyn, Karl, The Bramble Bush: On Our Law and Its Study 66–69 (Dobbs Ferry, N.Y.: Oceana Publishing 1960) (same).Google Scholar
Kronman, Anthony, The Lost Lawyer 109–62, 170–85, 209–25 (Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press 1995)Google Scholar
Fried, Charles, The Artificial Reason of the Law, or What Lawyers Know, 60 Tex. L. Rev. 35, 57 (1981).Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald, Law's Empire 228–32, 240–50, 254–58 (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press 1986)Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald, Taking Rights Seriously 22–31 (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press 1978)Google Scholar
Hart, Henry M. and Sacks, Albert M., The Legal Process: Basic Problems in the Making and Application of Law lxxix–lxxx, 545–96 (Eskridge, William N. and Frickey, Phillip P., eds., New York: Foundation Press 1994)Google Scholar
Burton, Steven, Judging in Good Faith 35–68 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1992)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pound, Roscoe, An Introduction to Legal Philosophy 56 (New Haven: Yale University Press 1922)Google Scholar
Henley, Kenneth, Abstract, Principles, Mid-Level Principles, and the Rule of Law, 12 L. & Phil. 121 (1993)Google Scholar
Eisenberg, Melvin Aron, The Nature of the Common Law 84 (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press 1988)Google Scholar
Westen, Peter, On “Confusing Ideas”: Reply, 91 Yale L.J. 1153, 1163 (1982)Google Scholar
Schauer, Frederick, Playing by the Rules: A Philosophical Examination of Rule-Based Decision-Making in Life and Law 183–87 (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1991)Google Scholar
Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice 14–21, 43–53, 578–82 (Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press 1971)Google Scholar
Lakoff, George and Johnson, Mark, Philosophy in the Flesh: The Embodied Mind and Its Challenge to Western Thought (New York: Basic Books 1999)Google Scholar
Lakoff, George and Johnson, Mark, Metaphors We Live By (Chicago: University of Chicago Press 1981).Google Scholar
Haidt, Jonathan, The Emotional Dog and Its Rational Tail: A Social Intuitionist Approach to Moral Judgment, 4 Psychological Review 814, 818 (2001)Google Scholar
Sloman, Steven A., Two Systems of Reasoning, in Heuristics and Biases: The Psychology of Intuitive Judgment 379 (Gilovich, Thomas, Griffin, Dale, and Kahneman, Daniel, eds., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2002)Google Scholar
Pound, Roscoe, Law Finding through Experience and Reason 45–65 (Athens: University of Georgia Press 1960)Google Scholar
Leiter, Brian, Heidegger and the Theory of Adjudication, 106 Yale L.J. 253, 259–61, 277–78 (1996)Google Scholar
Alexander, Larry, Constrained by Precedent, 63 S. Cal. L. Rev. 1, 29–30 (1989)Google Scholar
Hardin, Russell, Rational Choice, in II Encyclopedia of Ethics 1062, 1063–64 (Becker, Lawrence C. and Becker, Charlotte B., eds., New York: Garland Publishing 1992)Google Scholar
Dember, William N. and Warm, Joel S., The Psychology of Perception 113, 116–17 (2d ed., New York: Holt 1979)Google Scholar
Kahneman, Daniel and Tversky, Amos, Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision under Risk, 47 Econometrica 263, 277 (1979)Google Scholar
Treisman, Anne, Properties, Parts, and Objects, in II Handbook of Perception and Human Performance 35–34 (Boff, Kenneth R., Kaufman, Lloyd, and Thomas, James P., eds., New York: John Wiley & Sons 1986).Google Scholar
Simpson, A. W. B., The Ratio Decidendi of a Case and the Doctrine of Binding Precedent, in Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence 148, 160–63 (Guest, A. G., ed., Oxford: Oxford University Press 1961).Google Scholar
Perry, Stephen R., Two Models of Legal Principles, 82 Iowa L. Rev. 787, 807–8 (1997)Google Scholar
Alexander, Larry and Sherwin, Emily, The Rule of Rules: Morality, Rules, and the Dilemmas of Law 147 (Durham: Duke University Press 2001)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raz, Joseph, Ethics in the Public Domain 296 (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1996)Google Scholar
Alexander, Larry, Precedent, in A Companion to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory 503, 509 (Patterson, Dennis, ed., Cambridge, Mass.: Blackwell Publishers 1996).Google Scholar
Levenbook, Barbara Baum, The Meaning of a Precedent, 6 Legal Theory 185, 233–34 (2000)Google Scholar
Kress, Kenneth J., Legal Reasoning and Coherence Theories: Dworkin's Rights Thesis, Retroactivity, and the Linear Order of Decisions, 72 Cal. L. Rev. 369, 370 (1984)Google Scholar
Alexander, Larry and Kress, Ken, Against Legal Principles, in Law and Interpretation: Essays in Legal Philosophy 301–6 (Marmor, Andrei, ed., Oxford: Clarendon Press 1995).Google Scholar
Hurley, S. L., Coherence, Hypothetical Cases, and Precedent, 10 Oxford J. of Legal Stud. 221 (1990)Google Scholar
Fiss, Owen, Objectivity and Interpretation, 34 Stan. L. Rev. 739, 744–50 (1982).Google Scholar
Moore, Michael S., Legal Principles Revisited, 82 Iowa L. Rev. 867, 872–89 (1997).Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×