Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 December 2013
Analytic philosophy is widely, and with good reason, thought of as having two points of origin. First, in the work of Gottlob Frege: with his systematic presentation of modern logic, his use of that logic to give an account of arithmetic, and his articulation of the philosophical views he takes to be required by his logic; second, in the work of Bertrand Russell and G. E. Moore at the very end of the nineteenth century and the beginning of the twentieth. Russell and Moore put forward a metaphysical view incorporating a strong form of realism and developed their philosophical views on that basis. Russell formulated modern logic and used it to account for mathematics; in both of these matters his view resembles Frege's, but was initially worked out independently; he subsequently sought to apply the same principles to an understanding of empirical knowledge. Moore put forward a strongly realist view of ethics and developed a conception of philosophical analysis.
So we may distinguish the British origins of analytic philosophy from its German origins. Under the former head we shall confine ourselves to discussion of Russell and Moore. Under the latter, however, we shall consider figures other than Frege. Frege's work was confined to logic, the philosophy of mathematics, and to what he took to be the philosophical implications of these subjects. Crucially, he makes no attempt at a systematic treatment of empirical knowledge. Furthermore, his direct influence was quite limited. (Although the philosophers who were directly influenced by him include Russell, Wittgenstein and Carnap.) For these reasons, even the most cursory account of the German origins of analytic philosophy must take some account of later thinkers who played a role in the development of Logical Empiricism (also known as Logical Positivism), especially Carnap, who had the most influence of any of the Logical Empiricists on the subsequent development of analytic philosophy.
To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.