Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-gq7q9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-17T05:21:49.740Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

2 - Revolution in science and the Newtonian revolution as historical concepts

from PART ONE - THE NEWTONIAN REVOLUTION AND THE NEWTONIAN STYLE

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 May 2010

Get access

Summary

The concept of revolution

Many historians of science believe that the concept of revolution in science is of fairly recent origin, but I have found that during some three centuries there has been a more or less unbroken tradition (though by no means shared by all scientists) of viewing scientific change as a sequence of revolutions. In the eighteenth century, when this tradition appears to have taken its first rise, the word “revolution” continued to be used, as in the past, as a technical term in mathematics and astronomy; but it also gained currency in a general sense in two very distinct meanings, both of which are found in writings about scientific change and in historical accounts of political events. Of these, one which came into general usage during the eighteenth century denotes a breach of continuity or a secular (i.e., noncyclical) change of real magnitude, usually accompanied–at least in political events–by violence. The other is the older sense, used in relation both to the history of science and the history of political events, signifying a cyclical phenomenon, a continuous sequence of ebb and flow, a kind of circulation and return, or a repetition. After 1789, the new meaning came to predominate, and ever since, “revolution” has commonly implied a radical change and a departure from traditional or accepted modes of thought, belief, action, social behavior, or political or social organization. Thus in early modern times there occurred a double transformation of “revolution” and the concept for which it is the name.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1981

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×