Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-7drxs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-22T09:16:56.881Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

5 - Does Disagreement Undermine Theism?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2014

Roger Trigg
Affiliation:
University of Oxford
Get access

Summary

THE ROLE OF REASON

Some theologians and philosophers pass too quickly from a sensus divinitatis to the idea of the Christian God. Alternatively, some of those dealing with the cognitive science of religion are so ready to turn to a naturalistic explanation of all religion that they are willing to lump everything in the one category. In both cases, the challenge of religious diversity can be quickly passed over. Theologians can ignore it by simply concentrating on the tenets of one religion. In the case of naturalism, an apparent scientific explanation may explain “religion” but goes nowhere in explaining “diversity.”

From a theological point of view, some see diversity as a greater obstacle to faith than the existence of evil in the world. If it seems difficult to imagine that a good God could allow so much human suffering, by the same token, why would a caring God be ready to leave so many humans in ignorance of His nature? The atheist can easily say that when there are so many competing beliefs about what is true of the gods, God, or whatever, there is no principled reason for preferring one over the other. They are all to be accounted equally false, an accidental effect of some external influence. When there is no agreed-on way of deciding between them, as there is in scientific method, why not dismiss them as catchy stories that may appeal to the human mind? The myths about the gods transmitted by Homer can easily, it seems, be put into that category. Why not every other story about God? The cognitive science of religion shows how the human mind can latch on to stories that are “minimally counterintuitive,” stories that catch our interest because they are unusual but not excessively so. We can easily remember them, whether they are about talking frogs or beings with supernatural powers.

Type
Chapter
Information
Religious Diversity
Philosophical and Political Dimensions
, pp. 77 - 95
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Locke, John, Essay Concerning Human Understanding, edited and abridged by Pringle-Pattison, A. S., Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1924, bk. 4, chap. 19, para. 9, p. 361Google Scholar
Hick, John, “An Iranaean Theodicy,” in Encountering Evil, ed. Davis, Stephen T., Westminster John Knox Press, Louisville, KY, 2001, p. 42Google Scholar
McKim, Robert, On Religious Diversity, Oxford University Press, New York, 2012, p. 3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKim, Robert, Religious Ambiguity and Religious Diversity, Oxford University Press, New York, 2001, p. xiCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Trigg, Roger, Reality at Risk: A Defence of Realism in Philosophy and the Sciences, 2nd ed., Hemel, Hempstead, 1989, p. 67Google Scholar
Popper, Karl, Objective Knowledge, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1972, p. 347Google Scholar
Cottingham, John, The Spiritual Dimension, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2005, p. 71CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Trigg, Roger, Religion in Public Life: Must Faith Be Privatized?Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2007Google Scholar
Trigg, Roger, Reason and Commitment, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1973Google Scholar
Tillich, Paul, The Shaking of the Foundations, Charles Scribner's Sons, New York, 1948, p. 53Google Scholar
Miller, Nicholas P., The Religious Roots of the First Amendment: Dissenting Protestants and the Separation of Church and State, Oxford University Press, New York, 2012, p. 9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, T. S., “Reflections on My Critics,” in Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, ed. Lakatos, I. and Musgrave, A., Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1970, pp. 266–267Google Scholar
Halett, Garth, One God of All?Continuum, New York, 2010, p. 117Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×