Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dlnhk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-20T13:57:00.946Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Nudging and educating: bounded axiological rationality in behavioral insights

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 March 2019

ALEJANDRO HORTAL*
Affiliation:
University of North Carolina at Greensboro, USA
*
*Correspondence to: University of North Carolina at Greensboro, College of Arts and Sciences – Lang. Lit. and Cultures, 1111 Spring Garden St, 2321 MHRA Building, NC 27402-6170, USA. Email: a_hortal@uncg.edu

Abstract

While it is broadly accepted that individuals are boundedly rational, the meaning of these boundaries and what to do about them has generated a debate between two different views: one that defends nudging as the best possible way to improve the outcome of people's decision and one that criticizes their use. This debate occurs at an instrumental level, conceiving decisions under a goal-oriented perspective. I propose that adding the role of values (axiological rationality) to the discussion can shed new light, not only on this debate, but also on nudges themselves, clarifying and enriching some arguments in the discussion about autonomy and efficiency. This approach will not only be more comprehensive, but it will also increase the effectiveness of nudges by tackling the different components of our rationality. Nudges should not only be goal-oriented; they should also be educational. Non-educational nudges should be used in conjunction with educational interventions. I will illustrate my position with two examples: vaccination policies and nudges in the use of seatbelts.

Type
Review Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2019

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adams, J. and Hillman, M. (2001), ‘The risk compensation theory and bicycle helmets’, Inj. Prev., 7: 8991.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Álvarez, J. F. (1992), ‘¿Es inteligente ser racional?’, Sist. Rev. Cienc. Soc., 7391.Google Scholar
Barton, A. and Grüne-Yanoff, T. (2015), ‘From Libertarian Paternalism to Nudging—and Beyond’, Rev. Philos. Psychol., 6: 341359.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boudon, R. (2012), ‘“Analytical sociology” and the explanation of beliefs’, Rev Sci Soc Fr Est, 50: 734.Google Scholar
Boudon, R. (2003), ‘Beyond Rational Choice Theory’, Annu. Rev. Sociol., 29: 121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boudon, R. (1998a), ‘Limitations of Rational Choice Theory’, Am. J. Sociol., 104: 817–28.10.1086/210087CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boudon, R. (1998b), Social Mechanisms without Black Boxes, in: Hedström, P. and Swedberg, R. (Eds.), Social Mechanisms: An Analytical Approach to Social Theory, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bovens, L. (2009), The Ethics of Nudge, in: Grüne-Yanoff, T. and Hansson, S. O. (Eds.), Preference Change, Theory and Decision Library, Netherlands: Springer, 207219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
CDC (n.d.), Policy Impact: Seat Belts | Motor Vehicle Safety | CDC Injury Center.Google Scholar
Colombo, M. (2018), Learning and Reasoning, in: Sprevak, M. and Colombo, M. (Eds.), The Routledge Handbook of the Computational Mind., Routledge, 381396.Google Scholar
Costa, D. L. and Kahn, M. E. (2013), ‘Energy Conservation “Nudges” and Environmentalist Ideology: Evidence from a Randomized Residential Electricity Field Experiment’, J. Eur. Econ. Assoc., 11: 680702.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Pinedo-Garcia, M. and Noble, J. (2008), ‘Beyond persons: extending the personal/subpersonal distinction to non-rational animals and artificial agents’, Biol. Philos., 23: 87100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dekker, E. and Remic, B. (2018), Two Types of Ecological Rationality: Or How to Best Combine Psychology and Economics (SSRN Scholarly Paper No. ID 3168433). Social Science Research Network, Rochester, NY.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Demeulenaere, P. (2014), ‘Are there many types of rationality? Pap’, Rev. Sociol., 99: 515528.Google Scholar
Dennett, D.C. (1969), Content and consciousness, Oxford, England: Humanities Press.Google Scholar
Drayson, Z. (2012), ‘The Uses and Abuses of the Personal/Subpersonal Distinction’, Philos. Perspect., 26: 118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Echeverría, J. and Álvarez, J. F. (2008), Bounded Rationality in Social Sciences, in: Agazzi, E. (Ed.), Epistemology and the Social, Rodopi, 173191.Google Scholar
Gigerenzer, G. (2015), ‘On the Supposed Evidence for Libertarian Paternalism’, Rev. Philos. Psychol., 123.Google ScholarPubMed
Gigerenzer, G. (2014), Risk Savvy: How to Make Good Decisions, Penguin.Google Scholar
Gigerenzer, G. (2007), Gut Feelings: The Intelligence of the Unconscious, New York: Viking.Google Scholar
Gigerenzer, G. (1996), ‘On narrow norms and vague heuristics: A reply to Kahneman and Tversky’, Psychol. Rev, 103: 592596.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gigerenzer, G. and Hoffrage, U. (1995), ‘How to improve Bayesian reasoning without instruction: Frequency formats’, Psychol. Rev, 102: 684704.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grill, K. (2014), ‘Expanding the Nudge: Designing Choice Contexts and Choice Contents’, Ration. Mark. Morals, 5: 139162.Google Scholar
Grüne-Yanoff, T. (2012), ‘Old wine in new casks: libertarian paternalism still violates liberal principles’, Soc. Choice Welf., 38: 635645.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grüne-Yanoff, T. and Hertwig, R. (2016), ‘Nudge Versus Boost: How Coherent are Policy and Theory? Minds Mach., 26: 149183.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hansen, P. G. and Jespersen, A. M. (2013), ‘Nudge and the Manipulation of Choice: A Framework for the Responsible Use of the Nudge Approach to Behaviour Change in Public Policy’, Eur. J. Risk Regul., 4: 3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hausman, D. M. and Welch, B. (2010), ‘Debate: To Nudge or Not to Nudge*’, J. Polit. Philos., 18: 123136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hertwig, R. (2017), ‘When to consider boosting: some rules for policy-makers. Behav’, Public Policy, 1: 143161.Google Scholar
Hertwig, R., Gigerenzer - Journal of behavioral decision, G., 1999 (1999), The'conjunction fallacy'revisited: How intelligent inferences look like reasoning errors. search.proquest.com.3.0.CO;2-M>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hertwig, R. and Grüne-Yanoff, T. (2017), ‘Nudging and Boosting: Steering or Empowering Good Decisions’, Perspect. Psychol. Sci., 12: 973986.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hortal, A. (2017), ‘Empiricism in Herbert Simon: “Administrative Behavior” within the evolution of the Models of Bounded and Procedural Rationality’, Braz. J. Polit. Econ. Econ. Política, 37: 719733.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahneman, D. (2011), Thinking, Fast and Slow, Macmillan.Google Scholar
Levy, N. (2017), ‘Nudges in a post-truth world’, J Med Ethics, 43: 495500.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lodge, M. and Wegrich, K. (2016), ‘The Rationality Paradox of Nudge: Rational Tools of Government in a World of Bounded Rationality’, Law Policy, 38: 250267.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Manzo, G. (2014), ‘Reason-based explanations and analytical sociology’, A rejoinder to Boudon. Pap. Rev. Sociol., 99: 529551.Google Scholar
Navin, M. C. (2017), ‘The Ethics of Vaccination Nudges in Pediatric Practice’, HEC Forum, 29: 4357.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nozick, R. (1993), The Nature of Rationality, Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
Oster, E. and Kocks, G. (2018), After a Debacle, How California Became a Role Model on Measles. N. Y. Times.Google Scholar
Peltzman, S. (1975), ‘The Effects of Automobile Safety Regulation’, J. Polit. Econ., 83: 677725.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Polonioli, A. (2016a), ‘Reconsidering the normative argument from bounded rationality’, Theory Psychol., 26: 287303.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Polonioli, A. (2016b), ‘Adaptive Rationality, Biases, and the Heterogeneity Hypothesis’, Rev. Philos. Psychol., 7: 787803.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Polonioli, A. (2015), ‘Stanovich's arguments against the “adaptive rationality” project: An assessment’, Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. Part C Stud. Hist. Philos. Biol. Biomed. Sci., 49: 5562.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Polonioli, A. (2012), ‘Gigerenzer's ‘external validity argument’ against the heuristics and biases program: an assessment’, Mind Soc, 11: 133148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roeser, S. (2012), ‘Risk communication, public engagement, and climate change: a role for emotions’, Risk Anal, 32: 10331040.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Samuels, R., Stich, S. and Bishop, M. (2002), Ending the rationality wars: how to make disputes about human rationality disappear?, in: Elio, R. (Ed.), Common Sense, Reasoning, & Rationality, Oxford University Press, 236268.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, A. (2009), The Idea of Justice, Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, A. (2002), Rationality and Freedom, Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.Google Scholar
Sen, A. (1997), ‘Maximization and the Act of Choice’, Econometrica, 65: 745779.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, A. (1993), ‘Internal Consistency of Choice’, Econometrica, 61: 495521.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, A. (1977), ‘Rational fools: A critique of the behavioral foundations of economic theory’, Philos Public Aff, 6: 317344.Google Scholar
Simon, H. (1982), Models of Bounded Rationality, Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sims, A. and Müller, T. M. (2018), ‘Nudge Versus Boost: A Distinctions without a Normative Difference’, Econ. Philos., 128.Google Scholar
Smith, V. L. (2008), Rationality in economics: constructivist and ecological forms, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sunstein, C. and Thaler, R. H. (2003), ‘Libertarian Paternalism Is Not an Oxymoron’, Univ Chic Law Rev, 70: 11591202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sunstein, C. R. (2015a), ‘The ethics of nudging’, Yale J Regul, 32: 413450.Google Scholar
Sunstein, C. R. (2015b), Nudging and Choice Architecture: Ethical Considerations. Yale J Regul Discussion paper No. 809.Google Scholar
Sunstein, C. R. (2014), Why Nudge?: The Politics of Libertarian Paternalism, Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Sunstein, C. R. (2013), ‘Nudges vs. shoves’, Harv Rev F, 127: 210.Google Scholar
Thaler, R. H. (2018), ‘Nudge, not sludge’, Science, 361: 431431.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thaler, R. H. and Sunstein, C. R. (2009), Nudge: Improving Decisions About Health, Wealth and Happiness, Penguin.Google Scholar
Tversky, A. and Kahneman, D. (1983), ‘Extensional versus intuitive reasoning: The conjunction fallacy in probability judgment’, Psychol. Rev., 293315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tversky, A. and Kahneman, D. (1974), ‘Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases’, Science, 185: 11241131.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Weber, M. (1978), Economy and Society: An Outline of Interpretive Sociology, University of California Press.Google Scholar
Wilkinson, T. M. (2012), ‘Nudging and Manipulation’, Polit. Stud., 61: 341355.CrossRefGoogle Scholar