Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-g7gxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-19T16:47:55.647Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

ONE-VARIABLE FRAGMENTS OF FIRST-ORDER LOGICS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2024

PETR CINTULA
Affiliation:
INSTITUTE OF COMPUTER SCIENCE CZECH ACADEMY OF SCIENCES PRAGUE, CZECH REPUBLIC E-mail: cintula@cs.cas.cz
GEORGE METCALFE
Affiliation:
MATHEMATICAL INSTITUTE UNIVERSITY OF BERN BERN, SWITZERLAND E-mail: george.metcalfe@unibe.ch
NAOMI TOKUDA
Affiliation:
MATHEMATICAL INSTITUTE UNIVERSITY OF BERN BERN, SWITZERLAND E-mail: naomi.tokuda@unibe.ch
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

The one-variable fragment of a first-order logic may be viewed as an “S5-like” modal logic, where the universal and existential quantifiers are replaced by box and diamond modalities, respectively. Axiomatizations of these modal logics have been obtained for special cases—notably, the modal counterparts $\mathrm {S5}$ and $\mathrm {MIPC}$ of the one-variable fragments of first-order classical logic and first-order intuitionistic logic, respectively—but a general approach, extending beyond first-order intermediate logics, has been lacking. To this end, a sufficient criterion is given in this paper for the one-variable fragment of a semantically defined first-order logic—spanning families of intermediate, substructural, many-valued, and modal logics—to admit a certain natural axiomatization. More precisely, an axiomatization is obtained for the one-variable fragment of any first-order logic based on a variety of algebraic structures with a lattice reduct that has the superamalgamation property, using a generalized version of a functional representation theorem for monadic Heyting algebras due to Bezhanishvili and Harding. An alternative proof-theoretic strategy for obtaining such axiomatization results is also developed for first-order substructural logics that have a cut-free sequent calculus and admit a certain interpolation property.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

1 Introduction

The one-variable fragment of any standard first-order logic—intermediate, substructural, many-valued, modal, or otherwise—consists of consequences in the logic constructed using one distinguished variable x, unary relation symbols, propositional connectives, and the quantifiers $(\forall {x})$ and $(\exists {x})$ . Such a fragment may be conveniently reformulated as a propositional modal logic by replacing occurrences of an atom $P(x)$ with a propositional variable p, and occurrences of $(\forall {x})$ and $(\exists {x})$ with $\Box $ and $\Diamond $ , respectively. Typically, this modal logic is algebraizable—that is, it enjoys soundness and completeness with respect to some suitable class of algebraic structures—and hence, unlike the full first-order logic, can be studied using the tools of universal algebra.

Any standard semantics for a first-order logic, where quantifiers range over domains of models, yields a relational semantics for the one-variable fragment. On the other hand, a Hilbert-style axiomatization does not (at least directly) yield an axiomatization for the fragment, since a derivation of a one-variable formula may involve additional variables. Axiomatizations are well known for the modal counterparts $\mathrm {S5}$ [Reference Halmos16] and $\mathrm {MIPC}$ [Reference Bull4, Reference Monteiro and Varsavsky22] of the one-variable fragments of first-order classical logic and first-order intuitionistic logic, respectively, and similar results have been obtained for the modal counterparts of one-variable fragments of other first-order intermediate logics [Reference Bezhanishvili1, Reference Bezhanishvili and Harding2, Reference Caicedo, Metcalfe, Rodríguez and Rogger5Reference Caicedo and Rodríguez7, Reference Ono and Suzuki24, Reference Suzuki27, Reference Suzuki28] and many-valued logics [Reference Castaño, Cimadamore, Varela and Rueda8, Reference Di Nola and Grigolia12, Reference Metcalfe, Tuyt, Olivetti, Negri, Sandu and Verbrugge21, Reference Rutledge26]. However, a general approach to the problem of axiomatizing one-variable fragments of first-order logics has been lacking.Footnote 1

In this paper, we address this problem for a broad family of semantically defined first-order logics. In Section 2, we introduce (one-variable) first-order logics via models defined over classes of $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices: structures for an algebraic signature $\mathcal {L}$ with a lattice reduct. In particular, first-order intermediate logics and first-order substructural logics can be defined over classes of Heyting algebras and $\mathsf {FL_e}$ -algebras, respectively. For the sake of generality (e.g., when $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices are just lattices), consequence is defined for equations between two first-order formulas; however, this often (e.g., for any intermediate or substructural logic) corresponds to the usual notion of consequence between formulas.

In Section 3, we introduce potential axiomatizations for consequence in the modal counterparts of the one-variable fragments of these semantically defined logics. We define an m- $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice to be an $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice expanded with modalities $\Box $ and $\Diamond $ satisfying certain equations familiar from modal logic, and given any class $\mathsf {K}$ of $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices, let $\mathsf {mK}$ denote the class of m- $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices with an $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice reduct in $\mathsf {K}$ . For example, if $\mathsf {K}$ is a variety of Heyting algebras, then $\mathsf {mK}$ is a variety of monadic Heyting algebras in the sense of [Reference Monteiro and Varsavsky22]. We then show that m- $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices are in one-to-one correspondence with $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices equipped with a subalgebra satisfying a relative completeness condition, generalizing previous results in the literature (see, e.g., [Reference Bezhanishvili1, Reference Tuyt29]). We also show that if $\mathsf {K}$ is any class of $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices closed under taking subalgebras and direct powers (in particular, any variety), then consequence in the one-variable fragment of the first-order logic defined over $\mathsf {K}$ corresponds to consequence in the functional members of $\mathsf {mK}$ : m- $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices consisting of functions from a set W to an $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice $\mathbf {A}\in \mathsf {K}$ .

In Section 4, we close the circle, obtaining an axiomatization of consequence in the one-variable fragment of any first-order logic defined over a variety $\mathsf {V}$ of $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices that has the superamalgamation property: an algebraic property that is equivalent in some settings to the logical Craig interpolation property. We show that every member of $\mathsf {mV}$ is functional—generalizing a representation theorem of Bezhanishvili and Harding for monadic Heyting algebras [Reference Bezhanishvili and Harding2]—and hence that the defining equations for $\mathsf {mV}$ provide the desired axiomatization. In particular, we axiomatize the one-variable fragments of a broad range of first-order logics, including the seven consistent first-order intermediate logics that have Craig interpolation, first-order extensions of substructural logics such as $\mathsf {FL_e}$ , $\mathsf {FL_{ew}}$ , and $\mathsf {FL_{ec}}$ , a first-order lattice logic, and a first-order version of the modal logic $\mathrm {K}$ .

In Section 5, we present an alternative proof-theoretic strategy for establishing completeness of an axiomatization for the one-variable fragment of a first-order logic, the key idea being to show that additional variables can be eliminated from derivations of one-variable formulas in a suitable sequent calculus. As a concrete example, we obtain a new completeness proof for the one-variable fragment of the first-order version of the substructural logic $\mathrm {FL_e}$ by establishing an interpolation property for derivations in a cut-free sequent calculus. We then explain how the proof generalizes to a family of first-order substructural logics, including $\mathrm {FL_{ew}}$ , $\mathrm {FL_{ec}}$ , and $\mathrm {FL_{ewc}}$ (intuitionistic logic). Finally, in Section 6, we discuss the limitations of the methods described in the paper and potential extensions to broader families of first-order logics.

2 A family of first-order logics

Let $\mathcal {L}$ be any algebraic signature, and let $\mathcal {L}_n$ denote the set of operation symbols of $\mathcal {L}$ of arity $n\in \mathbb {N}$ . We will assume throughout this paper that $\mathcal {L}_2$ contains distinct symbols and , referring to such a signature as lattice-oriented.

We call an algebraic structure an $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice if $\star ^{\mathbf {A}}$ is an n-ary operation on A for each $\star \in \mathcal {L}_n$ ( $n\in \mathbb {N}$ ), and is a lattice with respect to the induced order . As usual, superscripts will be omitted when these are clear from the context.

Example 2.1. Let $\mathcal {L}_s$ be the lattice-oriented signature with binary operation symbols , , $\cdot $ , and $\to $ , and constant symbols $\mathrm {f}$ and $\mathrm {e}$ . An $\mathsf {FL_e}$ -algebra—also referred to as a commutative pointed residuated lattice—is an $\mathcal {L}_s$ -lattice such that is a commutative monoid and $\to $ is the residuum of $\cdot $ , that is, , for all $a,b,c\in ~A$ . The class of $\mathsf {FL_e}$ -algebras forms a variety $\mathsf {FL_e}$ that provides algebraic semantics for the full Lambek calculus with exchange $\mathrm {FL_e}$ —also known as multiplicative additive intuitionistic linear logic without additive constants (see, e.g., [Reference Galatos, Jipsen, Kowalski and Ono13, Reference Metcalfe, Paoli and Tsinakis20]). Algebraic semantics for other well-known substructural logics are provided by various subvarieties of $\mathsf {FL_e}$ ; e.g.

  • the full Lambek calculus with exchange and weakening $\mathrm {FL_{ew}}$ , and full Lambek calculus with exchange and contraction $\mathrm {FL_{ec}}$ , correspond to the varieties $\mathsf {FL_{ew}}$ and $\mathsf {FL_{ec}}$ of $\mathsf {FL_e}$ -algebras satisfying the equations , and , respectively;

  • intuitionistic logic $\mathrm {IL}$ corresponds to the variety $\mathsf {HA}$ of Heyting algebras, term-equivalent to $\mathsf {FL_{ewc}}=\mathsf {FL_{ew}}\cap \mathsf {FL_{ec}}$ (just identify $\cdot $ and );

  • classical logic $\mathrm {CL}$ and Gödel logic $\mathrm {G}$ correspond to the varieties $\mathsf {BA}$ of Boolean algebras, and $\mathsf {GA}$ of Gödel algebras, axiomatized relative to $\mathsf {HA}$ by the equations $(x\to \mathrm {f})\to \mathrm {f}\approx x$ and , respectively;

  • Łukasiewicz logic corresponds to the variety $\mathsf {MV}$ of MV-algebras, term-equivalent to the variety of $\mathsf {FL_{ew}}$ -algebras satisfying the equation .

Full first-order logics can be defined over an arbitrary predicate language with formulas built using propositional connectives from the algebraic signature $\mathcal {L}$ (see, e.g., [Reference Cintula and Noguera11, Section 7.1]). However, it suffices here to restrict our attention to the one-variable setting and a fixed (generic) predicate language. Let $\mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1}(\mathcal {L})$ denote the set of one-variable $\mathcal {L}$ -formulas $\varphi ,\psi ,\chi ,\dots $ built inductively using a countably infinite set of unary predicates $\{P_i\}_{i\in \mathbb {N}}$ , a distinguished variable x, connectives in $\mathcal {L}$ , and quantifiers $\forall ,\exists $ . We call an ordered pair of one-variable $\mathcal {L}$ -formulas $\varphi ,\psi \in \mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1}(\mathcal {L})$ , written $\varphi \approx \psi $ , an $\mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1}(\mathcal {L})$ -equation, and write as an abbreviation for .Footnote 2

Now let $\mathbf {A}$ be any $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice, let S be a non-empty set, and let $\mathcal {I}(P_i)$ be a map from S to A for each $i\in \mathbb {N}$ , writing $u\mapsto f(u)$ to denote a map assigning to each $u\in S$ some $f(u)\in A$ . We call the ordered pair an $\mathbf {A}$ -structure if the following inductively defined partial map is total:

If $\mathbf {A}$ is complete—that is, $\bigwedge X$ and $\bigvee X$ exist in A, for all $X \subseteq A$ —then is always an $\mathbf {A}$ -structure; otherwise, whether or not the partial map is total depends on $\mathcal {I}$ . E.g., for and $S=\mathbb {N}$ , if , for all $n\in \mathbb {N}$ , then is undefined, but if for all $i\in \mathbb {N}$ and $n\in S$ , for some fixed $K\in \mathbb {N}$ , then ${\mathfrak {{S}}}$ is an $\mathbf {A}$ -structure.

We say that an $\mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1}(\mathcal {L})$ -equation $\varphi \approx \psi $ is valid in an $\mathbf {A}$ -structure ${\mathfrak {{S}}}$ , and write ${\mathfrak {{S}}}\models \varphi \approx \psi $ , if . More generally, consider any class of $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices $\mathsf {K}$ . We say that an $\mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1}(\mathcal {L})$ -equation $\varphi \approx \psi $ is a (sentential) semantical consequence of a set of $\mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1}(\mathcal {L})$ -equations T in $\mathsf {K}$ , and write $T\vDash ^{\forall }_{\mathsf {K}}\varphi \approx \psi $ , if for any $\mathbf {A}\in \mathsf {K}$ and $\mathbf {A}$ -structure ${\mathfrak {{S}}}$ ,

In certain cases, we can restrict our attention to the complete members of $\mathsf {K}$ . Let us say that $\mathsf {K}$ admits regular completions if, for any $\mathbf {A}\in \mathsf {K}$ , there exists an $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice embedding h of $\mathbf {A}$ into a complete member $\mathbf {B}$ of $\mathsf {K}$ that preserves all existing meets and joins, noting that for any $\mathbf {A}$ -structure , the $\mathbf {B}$ -structure , with for each $i\in I$ , satisfies for all $\varphi \in \mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1}(\mathcal {L})$ . Clearly, semantical consequence in such a class $\mathsf {K}$ coincides with semantical consequence in the class of complete members of $\mathsf {K}$ .

Example 2.2. A sufficient, but by no means necessary, condition for a class of $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices to admit regular completions is closure under MacNeille completions (see, e.g., [Reference Harding17]). This is the case in particular for $\mathsf {BA}$ and $\mathsf {HA}$ ; indeed, they are the only non-trivial varieties of Heyting algebras that have this property [Reference Bezhanishvili and Harding3]. A broad family of varieties of $\mathsf {FL_e}$ -algebras—including $\mathsf {FL_e}$ , $\mathsf {FL_{ew}}$ , and $\mathsf {FL_{ec}}$ —are also closed under MacNeille completions, and for a still broader family—including $\mathsf {GA}$ —this is true for the class of their subdirectly irreducible members [Reference Ciabattoni, Galatos and Terui9]. Note, however, that in some cases—e.g., $\mathsf {MV}$ [Reference Gehrke and Priestley14]—neither the variety nor the class of its subdirectly irreducible members admits regular completions.

Let $\mathrm {Fm}_{\Box }(\mathcal {L})$ denote the set of propositional formulas $\alpha ,\beta ,\dots $ built inductively using a countably infinite set of propositional variables $\{p_i\}_{i\in \mathbb {N}}$ , connectives in $\mathcal {L}$ , and unary connectives $\Box $ and $\Diamond $ , and call an ordered pair of propositional formulas $\alpha ,\beta \in \mathrm {Fm}_{\Box }(\mathcal {L})$ , written $\alpha \approx \beta $ , an $\mathrm { Fm}_{\Box }(\mathcal {L})$ -equation. The (standard) translation functions $({-})^\ast $ and $({-})^\circ $ between $\mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1}(\mathcal {L})$ and $\mathrm {Fm}_{\Box }(\mathcal {L})$ are defined inductively by

$$ \begin{align*} (P_i(x))^\ast &= p_i & p_i^\circ &= P_i(x) & i\in\mathbb{N},\\ (\star(\varphi_1,\dots,\varphi_n))^\ast &= \star(\varphi^\ast_1,\dots,\varphi^\ast_n) & (\star(\alpha_1,\dots,\alpha_n))^\circ &= \star(\alpha^\circ_1,\dots,\alpha^\circ_n) & \star\in\mathcal{L}_n,\\ ((\forall{x}) \varphi)^\ast &=\Box \varphi^\ast & (\Box\alpha)^\circ &= (\forall{x}) \alpha^\circ, \\ ((\exists{x}) \varphi)^\ast &=\Diamond \varphi^\ast & (\Diamond\alpha)^\circ &= (\exists{x}) \alpha^\circ, \end{align*} $$

and lift in the obvious way to (sets of) $\mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1}(\mathcal {L})$ -equations and $\mathrm {Fm}_{\Box }(\mathcal {L})$ -equations.

Clearly, $(\varphi ^\ast )^\circ = \varphi $ for any $\varphi \in \mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1}(\mathcal {L})$ and $(\alpha ^\circ )^\ast = \alpha $ for any $\alpha \in \mathrm {Fm}_{\Box }(\mathcal {L})$ , and we may therefore switch between first-order and modal notations as convenient. To axiomatize consequence in the one-variable first-order logic based on a class of $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices $\mathsf {K}$ , it therefore suffices to find a (natural) axiomatization of a class $\mathsf {C}$ of algebras in the signature of $\mathcal {L}$ expanded with $\Box ,\Diamond $ such that $\vDash ^{\forall }_{\mathsf {K}}$ corresponds to equational consequence in $\mathsf {C}$ . More precisely, let us call a homomorphism from the formula algebra with universe $\mathrm {Fm}_{\Box }(\mathcal {L})$ to some $\mathbf {A}\in \mathsf {C}$ an $\mathbf {A}$ -evaluation, and define for any set $\mathrm {\Sigma }\cup \{\alpha \approx \beta \}$ of $\mathrm {Fm}_{\Box }(\mathcal {L})$ -equations,

Our goal in this paper is to provide a (natural) axiomatization of a variety $\mathsf {V}$ such that for any set of $\mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1}(\mathcal {L})$ -equations $T\cup \{\varphi \approx \psi \}$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} T\vDash^{\forall}_{\mathsf{K}}\varphi\approx\psi\:\iff\:T^\ast\vDash_{\mathsf{V}}\varphi^\ast\approx\psi^\ast. \end{align*} $$

Example 2.3. If $\mathsf {K}$ is $\mathsf {BA}$ , then $\vDash ^{\forall }_{\mathsf {K}}$ is consequence in the one-variable fragment of first-order classical logic, corresponding to $\mathrm {S5}$ , and $\mathsf {V}$ is the variety of monadic Boolean algebras defined in [Reference Halmos16]. If $\mathsf {K}$ is $\mathsf {HA}$ , then $\vDash ^{\forall }_{\mathsf {K}}$ is consequence in the one-variable fragment of first-order intuitionistic logic, corresponding to $\mathrm {MIPC}$ , and $\mathsf {V}$ is the variety of monadic Heyting algebras defined in [Reference Monteiro and Varsavsky22]. Analogous results have been obtained for first-order intermediate logics in [Reference Bezhanishvili1, Reference Bezhanishvili and Harding2, Reference Caicedo, Metcalfe, Rodríguez and Rogger5Reference Caicedo and Rodríguez7, Reference Ono and Suzuki24, Reference Suzuki27, Reference Suzuki28]. In particular, if $\mathsf {K}$ is $\mathsf {GA}$ , then $\vDash ^{\forall }_{\mathsf {K}}$ is consequence in the one-variable fragment of the first-order logic of linear frames, and $\mathsf {V}$ is the variety of monadic Heyting algebras satisfying the prelinearity axiom [Reference Caicedo, Metcalfe, Rodríguez and Tuyt6]. However, if $\mathsf {K}$ is the class of totally ordered members of $\mathsf {GA}$ , then $\vDash ^{\forall }_{\mathsf {K}}$ is consequence in the one-variable fragment of first-order Gödel logic, the first-order logic of linear frames with a constant domain, and $\mathsf {V}$ is the variety of monadic Gödel algebras, i.e., monadic Heyting algebras satisfying the prelinearity axiom and the constant domain axiom [Reference Caicedo and Rodríguez7]. Similarly, if $\mathsf {K}$ is the class of totally ordered MV-algebras, then $\vDash ^{\forall }_{\mathsf {K}}$ is consequence in the one-variable fragment of first-order Łukasiewicz logic, and $\mathsf {V}$ is the variety of monadic MV-algebras [Reference Rutledge26].

3 An algebraic approach

As our basic modal structures, let us define an m-lattice to be any algebraic structure with lattice reduct that satisfies the following equations:

Let stand for . It is easily shown that every m-lattice also satisfies the following equations and quasi-equations:

Now let $\mathcal {L}$ be any fixed lattice-oriented signature. We define an m- $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice to be any algebraic structure such that $\mathbf {A}$ is an $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice, is an m-lattice, and the following equation is satisfied for each $n\in \mathbb {N}$ and $\star \in \mathcal {L}_n$ :

$$\begin{align*}\begin{array}{rl} (\star_\Box) & \Box(\star(\Box x_1,\dots,\Box x_{n}))\approx\star(\Box x_1,\dots,\Box x_{n}). \end{array} \end{align*}$$

Using ( $\star _\Box $ ), $\mathrm {(L3_\Box )}$ , and (L3 $_\Diamond $ ), it follows that also satisfies for each $n\in \mathbb {N}$ and $\star \in \mathcal {L}_n$ , the equation

$$\begin{align*}\begin{array}{rl} (\star_\Diamond) & \Diamond(\star(\Diamond x_1,\dots,\Diamond x_{n}))\approx\star(\Diamond x_1,\dots,\Diamond x_{n}). \end{array} \end{align*}$$

Given a class $\mathsf {K}$ of $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices, let $\mathsf {mK}$ denote the class of m- $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices with an $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice reduct in $\mathsf {K}$ . Note that if $\mathsf {K}$ is a variety, then so is $\mathsf {mK}$ .

Example 3.1. It is straightforward to show that the notion of an m- $\mathcal {L}_s$ -lattice encompasses other algebraic structures considered in the literature. In particular, $\mathsf {mHA}$ and $\mathsf {mBA}$ are the varieties of monadic Heyting algebras [Reference Monteiro and Varsavsky22] and monadic Boolean algebras [Reference Halmos16], respectively. Moreover, if $\mathbf {A}$ is an $\mathsf {FL_e}$ -algebra, then every m- $\mathcal {L}_s$ -lattice satisfies the equations

$$\begin{align*}\begin{array}{r@{\quad}l@{\qquad}r@{\quad}l} \mathrm{(L6_\Box)} &\Box (x\to \Box y) \approx\Diamond x \to\Box y, & \mathrm{(L6_\Diamond)} & \Box (\Box x\to y) \approx\Box x \to\Box y, \end{array} \end{align*}$$

and $\mathsf {mFL_e}$ is therefore the variety of monadic $\mathsf {FL_e}$ -algebras introduced in [Reference Tuyt29]. Let us just check (L6 $_\Box $ ), the proof for (L6 $_\Diamond $ ) being very similar. Consider any $a,b\in A$ . Since , by (L1 $_\Diamond $ ), also . Hence, using (L3 $_\Box $ ), ( $\to _\Box $ ), and (L5 $_\Box $ ),

Conversely, since , by (L1 $_\Box $ ), it follows by residuation that and hence, using (L5 $_\Diamond $ ), (L3 $_\Diamond $ ), and ( $\to _\Diamond $ ),

By residuation again, .

Example 3.2. The variety $\mathsf {mGA}$ corresponds to the one-variable fragment of Corsi’s first-order logic of linear frames [Reference Caicedo, Metcalfe, Rodríguez and Tuyt6], whereas the variety of monadic Gödel algebras—axiomatized relative to $\mathsf {mGA}$ by the constant domain axiom—corresponds to the one-variable fragment of first-order Gödel logic, the first-order logic of linear frames with a constant domain [Reference Caicedo and Rodríguez7]. Note, however, that the variety axiomatized relative to $\mathsf {mMV}$ by the constant domain axiom does not satisfy $\Diamond x \cdot \Diamond x \approx \Diamond (x \cdot x)$ and therefore properly contains the variety of monadic MV-algebras studied in [Reference Castaño, Cimadamore, Varela and Rueda8, Reference Di Nola and Grigolia12, Reference Rutledge26]. Consider, for example, the MV-algebra (in the language of $\mathsf {FL_e}$ -algebras) with the usual order, where $a\cdot b:=\max (0,a+b-1)$ and $a\to b:=\min (1,1-a+b)$ . Let $\Box 0 = \Box \frac 12= \Diamond 0 = 0$ and $\Box 1=\Diamond \frac 12=\Diamond 1 =1$ . Then satisfies the constant domain axiom, but $\Diamond \frac 12\cdot \Diamond \frac 12= 1\cdot 1=1\neq 0=\Diamond 0=\Diamond (\frac 12\cdot \frac 12)$ .

We now provide a useful description of m- $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices that generalizes results in the literature for varieties such as monadic Heyting algebras [Reference Bezhanishvili1] and monadic $\mathsf {FL_e}$ -algebras [Reference Tuyt29].

Lemma 3.3. Let be any m- $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice. Then forms a subalgebra $\Box \mathbf {A}$ of $\mathbf {A}$ , where and,

Proof The fact that $\Box A$ forms a subalgebra of $\mathbf {A}$ follows directly using ( $\star _\Box $ ) for each operation symbol $\star $ of $\mathcal {L}$ , and $\Box A =\Diamond A$ follows from (L3 $_\Box $ ) and (L3 $_\Diamond $ ). Now consider any $a\in A$ . If $b\in \Box A$ satisfies , then , by (L4 $_\Box $ ) and (L5 $_\Box $ ). But , by (L1 $_\Box $ ), so . Analogous reasoning establishes that .

Let us call a sublattice $\mathbf {L}_0$ of a lattice $\mathbf {L}$ relatively complete if for any $a\in L$ , the set contains a maximum and the set contains a minimum. Equivalently, $\mathbf {L}_0$ is relatively complete if the inclusion map $f_0$ from to has left and right adjoints, that is, if there exist order-preserving maps $\Box \colon L\to L_0$ and $\Diamond \colon L\to L_0$ such that for all $a\in L$ and $b\in L_0$ ,

Let us also say that a subalgebra $\mathbf {A}_0$ of an $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice $\mathbf {A}$ is relatively complete if this property holds with respect to their lattice reducts. In particular, by Lemma 3.3, the subalgebra $\Box \mathbf {A}$ of $\mathbf {A}$ is relatively complete for any m- $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice . The following result establishes a converse.

Lemma 3.4. Let $\mathbf {A}_0$ be a relatively complete subalgebra of an $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice $\mathbf {A}$ , and define and for each $a\in A$ . Then is an m- $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice and $\Box _0 A =\Diamond _0 A = A_0$ .

Proof It is straightforward to check that is an m-lattice; for example, it satisfies (L2 $_\Box $ ), since for any $a_1,a_2\in A$ ,

Since $\mathbf {A}_0$ is a subalgebra of $\mathbf {A}$ , clearly also satisfies ( $\star _\Box $ ). Hence is an m- $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice and $\Box _0 A =\Diamond _0 A = A_0$ .

Combining Lemmas 3.3 and 3.4 yields the following representation theorem for m- $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices.

Theorem 3.5. Let $\mathsf {K}$ be any class of $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices. Then there exists a one-to-one correspondence between the members of $\mathsf {mK}$ and ordered pairs such that $\mathbf {A}\in \mathsf {K}$ and $\mathbf {A}_0$ is a relatively complete subalgebra of $\mathbf {A}$ , implemented by the maps and .

Next, given any $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice $\mathbf {A}$ and set W, let $\mathbf {A}^W$ be the $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice with universe $A^W$ , where the operations are defined pointwise.

Proposition 3.6. Let $\mathbf {A}$ be an $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice, W a set, and $\mathbf {B}$ a subalgebra of $\mathbf {A}^W$ such that for each $f\in B$ , the elements $\bigwedge _{v\in W}f(v)$ and $\bigvee _{v\in W}f(v)$ exist in $\mathbf {A}$ and the following constant functions belong to B:

$$ \begin{align*} \Box f\colon W\to A;\:u\mapsto\bigwedge_{v\in W} f(v) \quad\text{and}\quad\Diamond f\colon W\to A;\:u\mapsto\bigvee_{v\in W}f(v). \end{align*} $$

Then is an m- $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice, and if $\mathbf {A}$ belongs to a class $\mathsf {K}$ of $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices closed under taking subalgebras and direct powers, .

Proof It is straightforward to check that satisfies $\mathrm {(L1_\Box )}$ , $\mathrm {(L2_\Box )}$ , $\mathrm {(L1_\Diamond )}$ , and $\mathrm {(L2_\Diamond )}$ . To confirm that is an m- $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice—and therefore, if $\mathbf {A}$ belongs to a class $\mathsf {K}$ of $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices closed under taking subalgebras and direct powers, a member of $\mathsf {mK}$ —observe that $\Box f$ and $\Diamond f$ are, by definition, constant functions for any $f\in B$ . Hence clearly also satisfies $\mathrm {(L3_\Box )}$ and $\mathrm { (L3_\Diamond )}$ . Moreover, for any $n\in \mathbb {N}$ , $\star \in \mathcal {L}_n$ , and $f_1,\dots ,f_n\in B$ , the function $\star (\Box f_1,\dots ,\Box f_n)$ is constant and therefore equal to $\Box (\star (\Box f_1,\dots ,\Box f_n))$ , so satisfies ( $\star _\Box $ ).

Let us call an m- $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice -functional if it is constructed as described in Proposition 3.6 for some $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice $\mathbf {A}$ and set W. Given any class of $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices $\mathsf {K}$ , we call an m- $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice $\mathsf {K}$ -functional if it is isomorphic to an -functional m- $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice for some $\mathbf {A}\in \mathsf {K}$ and set W, omitting the prefix $\mathsf {K}$ - if the class is clear from the context.

The following result identifies the semantics of one-variable first-order logics with evaluations into functional m- $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices.

Proposition 3.7. Let $\mathbf {A}$ be any $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice.

  1. (a) Let be any $\mathbf {A}$ -structure. Then forms an -functional m- $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice $\mathbf {B}$ and the $\mathbf {B}$ -evaluation $g^{\mathfrak {{S}}}$ , defined by setting for each $i\in \mathbb {N}$ , satisfies for all $\varphi ,\psi \in \mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1}(\mathcal {L})$ ,

  2. (b) Let $\mathbf {B}$ be any -functional m- $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice for some set W, and let g be any $\mathbf {B}$ -evaluation. Then , where for each $i\in \mathbb {N}$ , is an $\mathbf {A}$ -structure satisfying for all $\varphi ,\psi \in \mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1}(\mathcal {L})$ ,

Proof (a) To show that $\mathbf {B}$ is -functional, it suffices to observe that for any , since ${\mathfrak {{S}}}$ is an $\mathbf {A}$ -structure, the elements and exist in $\mathbf {A}$ and correspond to the constant functions and , respectively. The fact that for all $\varphi \in \mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1}(\mathcal {L})$ , follows by an easy induction on the definition of $\varphi $ , from which it follows also that ${\mathfrak {{S}}}\models \varphi \approx \psi \iff g^{\mathfrak {{S}}}(\varphi ^\ast )=g^{\mathfrak {{S}}}(\psi ^\ast )$ , for all $\varphi ,\psi \in \mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1}(\mathcal {L})$ .

(b) Since $\mathbf {B}$ is -functional, the elements $\bigwedge _{v\in W}f(v)$ and $\bigvee _{v\in W}f(v)$ exist in $\mathbf {A}$ for every $f\in B$ . We prove that , by induction on the definition of $\varphi $ , from which it follows immediately that is an $\mathbf {A}$ -structure and ${\mathfrak {{W}}}\models \varphi \approx \psi \iff g(\varphi ^\ast )=g(\psi ^\ast )$ , for all $\varphi ,\psi \in \mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1}(\mathcal {L})$ . In particular, for the case where $\varphi =(\forall {x})\psi $ , using the induction hypothesis for the second line,

The case where $\varphi =(\exists {x})\psi $ is very similar.

Let $\mathsf {K}$ be any class of $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices and denote by $\mathsf {fK}$ the class of all $\mathsf {K}$ -functional m- $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices. Then, as a direct consequence of Proposition 3.7, for any set of $\mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1}(\mathcal {L})$ -equations $T\cup \{\varphi \approx \psi \}$ ,

If $\mathsf {K}$ is closed under taking subalgebras and direct powers, then $\mathsf {fK}\subseteq \mathsf {mK}$ , by Proposition 3.6, and we obtain the following relationship between consequence in the first-order logic defined over $\mathsf {K}$ and consequence in the variety $\mathsf {mK}$ .

Corollary 3.8. Let $\mathsf {K}$ be a class of $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices closed under taking subalgebras and direct powers. Then for any set of $\mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1}(\mathcal {L})$ -equations $T\cup \{\varphi \approx \psi \}$ ,

Moreover, if every member of $\mathsf {mK}$ is $\mathsf {K}$ -functional (i.e., $\mathsf {fK}=\mathsf {mK}$ ), then

Let us remark that a stricter notion of a functional algebra for a class $\mathsf {K}$ of $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices is considered in [Reference Bezhanishvili and Harding2, Reference Cintula, Metcalfe, Tokuda, Fernandéz-Duque, Palmigiano and Pinchinat10] that coincides in our setting with the notion of being $\mathsf {K}^c$ -functional, where $\mathsf {K}^c$ is the class of complete members of $\mathsf {K}$ . That is, an m- $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice is $\mathsf {K}^c$ -functional if it is isomorphic to a subalgebra of for some complete $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice $\mathbf {A}\in \mathsf {K}$ and set W, where $\Box $ and $\Diamond $ are defined as described in Proposition 3.6.

4 A functional representation theorem

Adapting the proof of a similar result for Heyting Algebras [Reference Bezhanishvili and Harding2, Theorem 3.6], we prove in this section that if a variety $\mathsf {V}$ of $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices has the superamalgamation property, then every member of $\mathsf {mV}$ is $\mathsf {V}$ -functional, and hence, by Corollary 3.8, consequence in the one-variable first-order logic defined over $\mathsf {V}$ corresponds to consequence in $\mathsf {mV}$ .

We first recall the necessary algebraic notions. Let $\mathsf {K}$ be a class of $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices. A V-formation in $\mathsf {K}$ is a $5$ -tuple consisting of $\mathbf {A},\mathbf {B}_1,\mathbf {B}_2\in \mathsf {K}$ and embeddings $f_1\colon \mathbf {A}\to \mathbf {B}_1$ , $f_2\colon \mathbf {A}\to \mathbf {B}_2$ . An amalgam in $\mathsf {K}$ of a V-formation in $\mathsf {K}$ is a triple consisting of $\mathbf {C}\in \mathsf {K}$ and embeddings $g_1\colon \mathbf {B}_1\to \mathbf {C}$ , $g_2\colon \mathbf {B}_2\to \mathbf {C}$ such that $g_1\circ f_1 = g_2\circ f_2$ ; it is called a superamalgam if also for any $b_1\in B_1$ , $b_2\in B_2$ and distinct $i,j\in \{1,2\}$ ,

The class $\mathsf {K}$ is said to have the superamalgamation property if every V-formation in $\mathsf {K}$ has a superamalgam in $\mathsf {K}$ .

Theorem 4.1. Let $\mathsf {K}$ be a class of $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices that is closed under taking direct limits and subalgebras, and has the superamalgamation property. Then every member of $\mathsf {mK}$ is functional.

Proof Consider any . Then $\mathbf {A}\in \mathsf {K}$ and, since $\mathsf {K}$ is closed under taking subalgebras, also $\Box \mathbf {A}\in \mathsf {K}$ . We let $W:=\mathbb {N}^{>0}$ and define inductively a sequence of $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices in $\mathsf {K}$ and sequences of $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice embeddings , , .

Let and let $f_0\colon \Box \mathbf {A}\to \mathbf {A}$ be the inclusion map. For each $i\in W$ , there exists inductively, by assumption, a superamalgam of the V-formation , and we define also .

Now let $\mathbf {L}$ be the direct limit of the system with an associated sequence of $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice embeddings . Since $\mathsf {K}$ is closed under taking direct limits, $\mathbf {L}$ belongs to $\mathsf {K}$ . The first two superamalgamation steps of this construction are depicted in the following diagram:

Since the operations of $\mathbf {L}^W$ are defined pointwise, is the universe of a subalgebra $\mathbf {B}$ of $\mathbf {L}^W$ . We can also show that for each $a\in A$ , the elements

$$ \begin{align*} \bigwedge_{j\in W}l_j\circ g_j(a)\quad\text{and}\quad\bigvee_{j\in W}l_j\circ g_j(a) \end{align*} $$

exist in L and hence that , with $\Box $ and $\Diamond $ defined in Proposition 3.6, is an -functional m- $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice. Let $a\in A$ and fix some $i\in W$ . It suffices to show that $l_i\circ g_i(\Box a)$ and $l_i\circ g_i(\Diamond a)$ are the greatest lower bound and the least upper bound, respectively, of . Observe first that for any $k\in W$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} l_k\circ g_k(\Box a)=l_k\circ f_k(\Box a)=l_{k+1}\circ s_{k+1}\circ f_k(\Box a)=l_{k+1}\circ g_{k+1}(\Box a), \end{align*} $$

where the first and last equations follow from the definition of $f_k$ and the second follows from the fact that $\mathbf {L}$ is a direct limit. Hence for each $j\in W$ ,

So $l_i\circ g_i(\Box a)$ is a lower bound of S. Now suppose that $c\in L$ is another lower bound of S. Since $\mathbf {L}$ is a direct limit, there exist $k\in W$ and $d\in A_k$ such that

Since $l_{k+1}$ is an embedding, . Hence, since is a superamalgam of , there exists $b\in \Box A$ such that

But $s_{k+1}$ and $g_{k+1}$ are embeddings and $f_0$ is the inclusion map, so and . The latter inequality together with $b\in \Box A$ , yields . Hence also , and, using the first inequality,

So $\bigwedge _{j\in W} l_j\circ g_j(a)=l_i\circ g_i(\Box a)$ exists in L and the constant function belongs to B. Also, symmetrically, $\bigvee _{j\in W}l_j\circ g_j(a)=l_i\circ g_i(\Diamond a)$ exists in L and the constant function belongs to B.

To show that is functional, it remains to prove that the following map is an isomorphism:

Since the operations of $\mathbf {L}^W$ are defined pointwise and $l_i$ and $g_i$ are $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice embeddings for each $i\in W$ , also f is an $\mathcal {L}$ -lattice embedding. Clearly, it is onto, by the definition of B. Moreover, recalling that $l_i\circ g_i(\Box a)=\bigwedge _{j\in W} l_i\circ g_i(a)$ for each $a\in A$ , it follows that

and, similarly, $f(\Diamond a)=\Diamond f(a)$ .

Combining Theorem 4.1 with Corollary 3.8 yields the following result.

Corollary 4.2. If $\mathsf {V}$ is a variety of $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices that has the superamalgamation property, then for any set $T\cup \{\varphi \approx \psi \}$ of $\mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1}(\mathcal {L})$ -equations,

Example 4.3. The variety of lattices has the superamalgamation property [Reference Grätzer15]. Hence, by Theorem 4.1, every m-lattice is functional, and consequence in the one-variable first-order lattice logic corresponds to consequence in m-lattices.

Example 4.4. $\mathsf {FL_e}$ , $\mathsf {FL_{ew}}$ , and $\mathsf {FL_{ec}}$ , and many other varieties of $\mathsf {FL_e}$ -algebras have the superamalgamation property, which is equivalent in this setting to the Craig interpolation property for the associated substructural logic (see, e.g., [Reference Galatos, Jipsen, Kowalski and Ono13]). Hence, for any such variety $\mathsf {V}$ —notably, for $\mathsf {V}\in \{\mathsf {FL_e},\mathsf {FL_{ew}},\mathsf {FL_{ec}}\}$ —every member of $\mathsf {mV}$ is functional, and consequence in the one-variable first-order substructural logic defined over $\mathsf {V}$ corresponds to consequence in $\mathsf {mV}$ .

Example 4.5. A normal modal logic has the Craig interpolation property if and only if the associated variety of modal algebras—Boolean algebras with an operator—has the superamalgamation property [Reference Maksimova19]. Moreover, there exist infinitely many such logics [Reference Rautenberg25], including well-known cases such as $\mathrm {K}$ , $\mathrm {KT}$ , $\mathrm {K4}$ , and $\mathrm {S4}$ . Hence our results yield axiomatizations for the one-variable fragments of infinitely many first-order logics defined over varieties of modal algebras.

Suppose finally that $\mathsf {K}$ is a class of $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices that is not only closed under taking direct limits and subalgebras and has the superamalgamation property, but also admits regular completions. In this case, we can adapt the proof of Theorem 4.1 to show that every member of $\mathsf {K}$ is $\mathsf {K}^c$ -functional, which—as noted at the end of Section 3—corresponds to the stricter notion of a functional algebra considered in [Reference Bezhanishvili and Harding2, Reference Cintula, Metcalfe, Tokuda, Fernandéz-Duque, Palmigiano and Pinchinat10]. Just observe that, given some , the direct limit $\mathbf {L}\in \mathsf {K}$ constructed in the proof embeds into some $\boldsymbol{\bar{\mathbf{L}}}\in \mathsf {K}^c$ and hence, reasoning as before, is isomorphic to a subalgebra of .

5 A proof-theoretic strategy

In this section, we describe an alternative proof-theoretic strategy for establishing completeness of axiomatizations for one-variable fragments of first-order logics. The key step is to prove that a derivation of a one-variable formula in a sequent calculus for the first-order logic can be transformed into a derivation that uses just one variable. To illustrate, we consider the first-order version of the full Lambek calculus with exchange $\mathrm {FL_e}$ , then extend the method to a broader family of first-order substructural logics.

The crucial feature of the first-order version of $\mathrm {FL_e}$ needed for our approach is the fact that it can be presented as a cut-free sequent calculus with the standard rules for quantifiers. Any derivation of a one-variable formula $\varphi $ in this calculus will therefore consist of sequents containing only subformulas of $\varphi $ with some free occurrences of the variable x replaced by other variables. In particular, the derivation will not introduce any new occurrences of quantifiers or bound variables, but may introduce free variables not occurring in $\varphi $ via the rules for the universal quantifier on the right and the existential quantifier on the left. Hence, to reason about derivations of one-variable formulas, we may consider a fragment of the sequent calculus restricted to formulas that contain only unary predicates and one bound variable, but may contain further free variables.

More formally, let $\mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1+}(\mathcal {L}_s)$ be the set of first-order formulas built inductively using unary predicates $\{P_i\}_{i\in \mathbb {N}}$ , variables $\{x\}\cup \{x_i\}_{i\in \mathbb {N}}$ , connectives in $\mathcal {L}_s$ , and quantifiers $(\forall {x})$ and $(\exists {x})$ . Clearly, $\mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1}(\mathcal {L}_s)\subseteq \mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1+}(\mathcal {L}_s)$ . We write $\varphi (\bar {w})$ to denote that the free variables of $\varphi \in \mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1+}(\mathcal {L}_s)$ belong to a set $\bar {w}$ , and indicate by $\varphi (\bar {w},y)$ that y is not among the variables in $\bar {w}$ .

For the purposes of this paper, we define a sequent to be an ordered pair of finite multisets of formulas $\mathrm {\Gamma },\mathrm {\Delta }$ in $\mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1+}(\mathcal {L}_s)$ , denoted by $\mathrm {\Gamma }{{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}\mathrm {\Delta }$ , such that $\mathrm {\Delta }$ contains at most one $\mathcal {L}_s$ -formula.Footnote 3 As usual, we denote the multiset sum of two finite multisets of formulas $\mathrm {\Gamma }_1$ and $\mathrm {\Gamma }_2$ by $\mathrm {\Gamma }_1,\mathrm {\Gamma }_2$ , and the empty multiset by an empty space. We also define, for $n\in \mathbb {N}^{>0}$ and $\varphi _1,\dots ,\varphi _n,\psi \in \mathrm { Fm}_{\forall }^{1+}(\mathcal {L}_s)$ ,

We write $\mathrm {\Gamma }(\bar {w})$ to denote that the free variables occurring in a finite multiset of formulas $\mathrm {\Gamma }$ belong to a set $\bar {w}$ .

The sequent calculus ${\mathrm {\forall 1FL_e}}$ is displayed in Figure 1, where the quantifier rules are subject to the following side-conditions:

  1. (i) If the conclusion of an application of $({\forall \,{\Rightarrow }})$ or $({\Rightarrow }\, \exists )$ contains at least one free occurrence of a variable, then the variable u occurring in its premise also occurs freely in its conclusion.

  2. (ii) The variable y occurring in the premise of an application of $({\Rightarrow }\, \forall )$ or $(\exists \, {\Rightarrow })$ does not occur freely in its conclusion.

If there exists a derivation d of a sequent $\mathrm {\Gamma }{{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}\mathrm {\Delta }$ in a sequent calculus $\mathrm {S}$ , we write $d\vdash _{_{\mathrm {S}}}\mathrm {\Gamma }{{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}\mathrm {\Delta }$ or simply $\vdash _{_{\mathrm {S}}}\mathrm {\Gamma }{{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}\mathrm {\Delta }$ .

Figure 1 The sequent calculus ${\mathrm {\forall 1FL_e}}$ .

The following relationship between derivability of sequents in ${\mathrm {\forall 1FL_e}}$ and (first-order) validity of equations in $\mathsf {FL_e}$ is a direct consequence of the completeness of a cut-free sequent calculus for the first-order version of $\mathrm {FL_e}$ .

Proposition 5.1 (cf. [Reference Komori18, Reference Ono and Komori23]).

For any sequent $\mathrm {\Gamma }{{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}\mathrm {\Delta }$ containing formulas from $\mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1}(\mathcal {L}_s)$ ,

We now establish an interpolation property for the calculus ${\mathrm {\forall 1FL_e}}$ . For any derivation d of a sequent in ${\mathrm {\forall 1FL_e}}$ , let ${\mathrm {md}}(d)$ denote the maximum number of applications of the rules $({\Rightarrow }\,\forall )$ and $(\exists \,{\Rightarrow })$ that occur on a branch of d. Note that the assumption in the following lemma that no variable in $\bar {w}\cup \{y,z\}$ lies in the scope of a quantifier is required for the proof to ensure that any formula $(\forall {x})\varphi (x)$ or $(\exists {x})\varphi (x)$ occurring in d contains no free variables; however, in order to deal with the cases of $({\Rightarrow }\,\forall )$ and $(\exists \,{\Rightarrow })$ , the formula $\chi (\bar {w})\in \mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1+}(\mathcal {L}_s)$ is not required to satisfy this condition.

Lemma 5.2. Let $\mathrm {\Gamma }(\bar {w},y),\Pi (\bar {w},z){{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}\mathrm {\Delta }(\bar {w},z)$ be any sequent such that $y\neq z$ , $x\not \in \bar {w}\cup \{y,z\}$ , and no variable in $\bar {w}\cup \{y,z\}$ lies in the scope of a quantifier. If $d\vdash _{_{\mathrm {\forall 1FL_e}}}\mathrm {\Gamma }(\bar {w},y),\Pi (\bar {w},z){{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}\mathrm {\Delta }(\bar {w},z)$ , then there exist ${\chi (\bar {w})\in \mathrm { Fm}_{\forall }^{1+}(\mathcal {L}_s)}$ and derivations $d_1,d_2$ in ${\mathrm {\forall 1FL_e}}$ such that and

$$ \begin{align*} d_1\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}(\bar{w},y){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\chi(\bar{w}), \quad d_2\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\Pi(\bar{w},z),\chi(\bar{w}){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\mathrm{\Delta}(\bar{w},z). \end{align*} $$

Proof By a straightforward inspection of the rules of ${\mathrm {\forall 1FL_e}}$ , no variable in $\bar {w}\cup \{y,z\}$ can lie in the scope of a quantifier in a sequent occurring in a derivation in ${\mathrm {\forall 1FL_e}}$ of $\mathrm {\Gamma }(\bar {w},y),\Pi (\bar {w},z){{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}\mathrm {\Delta }(\bar {w},z)$ . We prove the claim by induction on the height of d, considering in turn the last rule applied in the derivation.

Observe first that if y does not occur in $\mathrm {\Gamma }$ , we can define $\chi (\bar {w}):=\prod \mathrm {\Gamma }$ , and obtain a derivation $d_1$ of $\mathrm {\Gamma }(\bar {w},y){{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}\chi (\bar {w})$ , ending with repeated applications of $({\Rightarrow }\,\cdot )$ , $({\Rightarrow }\,\mathrm {e})$ , and , and a derivation $d_2$ of $\Pi (\bar {w},z),\chi (\bar {w}){{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}\mathrm {\Delta }(\bar {w},z)$ that extends d with repeated applications of $(\cdot \,{\Rightarrow })$ and $(\mathrm {e}\,{\Rightarrow })$ , such that ${\mathrm {md}}(d_1)=0$ and ${\mathrm {md}}(d_2)={\mathrm {md}}(d)$ . Similarly, if z does not occur in $\Pi ,\mathrm {\Delta }$ , we can define $\chi (\bar {w}):=\prod \Pi \to \sum \mathrm {\Delta }$ , and obtain a derivation $d_1$ of $\mathrm {\Gamma }(\bar {w},y){{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}\chi (\bar {w})$ that extends d with repeated applications of $(\cdot \,{\Rightarrow })$ , $(\mathrm {e}\,{\Rightarrow })$ , and $({\Rightarrow }\,\mathrm {f})$ , followed by an application of $({\Rightarrow }\to )$ , and a derivation $d_2$ of $\Pi (\bar {w},z),\chi (\bar {w}){{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}\mathrm {\Delta }(\bar {w},z)$ ending with repeated applications of , $({\Rightarrow }\,\cdot )$ , $({\Rightarrow }\,\mathrm {e})$ , and $(\mathrm {f}\,{\Rightarrow })$ , followed by an application of $(\to {\Rightarrow })$ , such that ${\mathrm {md}}(d_1)={\mathrm {md}}(d)$ and ${\mathrm {md}}(d_2)=0$ .

For the base cases where d ends with , $({\Rightarrow }\,\mathrm {e})$ , or $(\mathrm {f}\,{\Rightarrow })$ , either y does not occur in $\mathrm {\Gamma }$ or z does not occur in $\Pi ,\mathrm {\Delta }$ . For the remainder of the proof, let us assume that y occurs in $\mathrm {\Gamma }$ and z occurs in $\Pi ,\mathrm {\Delta }$ . The cases where d ends with an operational rule for one of the propositional connectives are all straightforward, so let us just consider $(\to {\Rightarrow })$ as an example.

Suppose for the first subcase that $\mathrm {\Gamma }(\bar {w},y)$ is $\mathrm {\Gamma }_1(\bar {w},y),\mathrm {\Gamma }_2(\bar {w},y),\varphi (\bar {w},y)\to \psi (\bar {w},y)$ and $\Pi (\bar {w},z)$ is $\Pi _1(\bar {w},z),\Pi _2(\bar {w},z)$ , and

$$ \begin{align*} d^{\prime}_1&\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}_1(\bar{w},y),\Pi_1(\bar{w},z){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\varphi(\bar{w},y),\\ d^{\prime}_2&\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}_2(\bar{w},y),\psi(\bar{w},y),\Pi_2(\bar{w},z){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\mathrm{\Delta}(\bar{w},z), \end{align*} $$

where . Two applications of the induction hypothesis produce $\chi _1(\bar {w}),\chi _2(\bar {w})\in \mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1+}(\mathcal {L}_s)$ and derivations $d^{\prime }_{11},d^{\prime }_{12},d^{\prime }_{21},d^{\prime }_{22}$ such that , , and

$$ \begin{align*} d^{\prime}_{11}\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}_1(\bar{w},y),\chi_1(\bar{w}){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\varphi(\bar{w},y), & \quad d^{\prime}_{12}\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\Pi_1(\bar{w},z){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\chi_1(\bar{w}),\\ d^{\prime}_{21}\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}_2(\bar{w},y),\psi(\bar{w},y){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\chi_2(\bar{w}), & \quad d^{\prime}_{22}\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\Pi_2(\bar{w},z),\chi_2(\bar{w}){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\mathrm{\Delta}(\bar{w},z). \end{align*} $$

Let $\chi (\bar {w}):=\chi _1(\bar {w})\to \chi _2(\bar {w})$ . Then $d^{\prime }_{11}$ and $d^{\prime }_{21}$ , together with applications of $(\to {\Rightarrow })$ and $({\Rightarrow }\to )$ , and $d^{\prime }_{12}$ and $d^{\prime }_{22}$ , together with an application of $(\to {\Rightarrow })$ , yield derivations $d_1$ and $d_2$ , respectively, such that and

$$ \begin{align*} & d_{1}\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}_1(\bar{w},y),\mathrm{\Gamma}_2(\bar{w},y),\varphi(\bar{w},y)\to\psi(\bar{w},y){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\chi(\bar{w}),\\ & d_{2}\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\Pi_1(\bar{w},z),\Pi_2(\bar{w},z),\chi(\bar{w}){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\mathrm{\Delta}(\bar{w},z). \end{align*} $$

For the second subcase, suppose that $\mathrm {\Gamma }(\bar {w},y)$ is $\mathrm {\Gamma }_1(\bar {w},y),\mathrm {\Gamma }_2(\bar {w},y)$ and $\Pi (\bar {w},z)$ is $\Pi _1(\bar {w},z),\Pi _2(\bar {w},z),\varphi (\bar {w},z)\to \psi (\bar {w},z)$ , and

$$ \begin{align*} d^{\prime}_1&\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}_1(\bar{w},y),\Pi_1(\bar{w},z){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\varphi(\bar{w},z),\\ d^{\prime}_2&\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}_2(\bar{w},y),\Pi_2(\bar{w},z),\psi(\bar{w},z){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\mathrm{\Delta}(\bar{w},z), \end{align*} $$

where . Two applications of the induction hypothesis produce $\chi _1(\bar {w}),\chi _2(\bar {w})\in \mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1+}(\mathcal {L}_s)$ and derivations $d^{\prime }_{11},d^{\prime }_{12},d^{\prime }_{21},d^{\prime }_{22}$ such that , , and

$$ \begin{align*} d^{\prime}_{11}\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}_1(\bar{w},y){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\chi_1(\bar{w}), & \quad d^{\prime}_{12}\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\Pi_1(\bar{w},z),\chi_1(\bar{w}){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\varphi(\bar{w},z),\\ d^{\prime}_{21}\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}_2(\bar{w},y){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\chi_2(\bar{w}), & \quad d^{\prime}_{22}\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\Pi_2(\bar{w},z),\psi(\bar{w},z),\chi_2(\bar{w}){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\mathrm{\Delta}(\bar{w},z). \end{align*} $$

Let $\chi (\bar {w}):=\chi _1(\bar {w})\cdot \chi _2(\bar {w})$ . Then $d^{\prime }_{11}$ and $d^{\prime }_{21}$ , together with an application of $({\Rightarrow }\,\cdot )$ , and $d^{\prime }_{12}$ and $d^{\prime }_{22}$ , together with applications of $(\to {\Rightarrow })$ and $(\cdot \,{\Rightarrow })$ , yield derivations $d_1$ and $d_2$ , respectively, such that and

$$ \begin{align*} & d_{1}\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}_1(\bar{w},y),\mathrm{\Gamma}_2(\bar{w},y){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\chi(\bar{w}),\\ & d_{2}\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\Pi_1(\bar{w},z),\Pi_2(\bar{w},z),\varphi(\bar{w},z)\to\psi(\bar{w},z),\chi(\bar{w}){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\mathrm{\Delta}(\bar{w},z). \end{align*} $$

Next, we consider all the cases where d ends with an application of one of the quantifier rules.

  • $({\forall \,{\Rightarrow }})$ : Suppose first that $\mathrm {\Gamma }(\bar {w},y)$ is $\mathrm {\Gamma }'(\bar {w},y),(\forall {x})\varphi (x)$ and

    $$ \begin{align*} d'\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}'(\bar{w},y),\varphi(u),\Pi(\bar{w},z){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\mathrm{\Delta}(\bar{w},z), \end{align*} $$
    where ${\mathrm {md}}(d')={\mathrm {md}}(d)$ and, using the assumption that no other variable lies in the scope of a quantifier, x is the only variable occurring in $\varphi $ . Since y occurs in $\mathrm {\Gamma }$ and z occurs in $\Pi ,\mathrm {\Delta }$ , it follows from side-condition (i) for $({\forall \,{\Rightarrow }})$ that $u\in \bar {w}\cup \{y,z\}$ . For the first subcase, suppose that $u\in \bar {w}\cup \{y\}$ . An application of the induction hypothesis produces $\chi (\bar {w})\in \mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1+}(\mathcal {L}_s)$ and derivations $d_1',d_2$ such that and
    $$ \begin{align*} d_1'\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}'(\bar{w},y),\varphi(u){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\chi(\bar{w}),\quad d_2\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\Pi(\bar{w},z),\chi(\bar{w}){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\mathrm{\Delta}(\bar{w},z). \end{align*} $$
    If u occurs in $\mathrm {\Gamma }'(\bar {w},y),\chi (\bar {w})$ , then extending $d_1'$ with an application of $({\forall \,{\Rightarrow }})$ yields a derivation $d_1$ such that and
    $$ \begin{align*} d_1\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}'(\bar{w},y),(\forall{x})\varphi(x){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\chi(\bar{w}). \end{align*} $$
    Otherwise, by substituting u uniformly with y in $d_1'$ , we obtain a derivation of $\mathrm {\Gamma }'(\bar {w},y),\varphi (y){{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}\chi (\bar {w})$ and obtain $d_1$ as described previously.

    For the second subcase, consider $u=z$ . An application of the induction hypothesis produces $\chi '(\bar {w})\in \mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1+}(\mathcal {L}_s)$ and derivations $d_1',d_2'$ such that and

    $$ \begin{align*} d_1'\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}'(\bar{w},y){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\chi'(\bar{w}), \quad d_2'\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\varphi(z),\Pi(\bar{w},z),\chi'(\bar{w}){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\mathrm{\Delta}(\bar{w},z). \end{align*} $$
    Let . Combining an instance $(\forall {x})\varphi (x)\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}(\forall {x})\varphi (x)$ of with $d_1'$ and an application of $({\Rightarrow }\,\cdot )$ yields a derivation $d_1$ such that and
    $$ \begin{align*} d_1\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}'(\bar{w},y),(\forall{x})\varphi(x){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\chi(\bar{w}). \end{align*} $$
    Also, $d_2'$ extended with applications of $({\forall \,{\Rightarrow }})$ and $(\cdot \,{\Rightarrow })$ yields a derivation $d_2$ such that and
    $$ \begin{align*} d_2\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\Pi(\bar{w},z),\chi(\bar{w}){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\mathrm{\Delta}(\bar{w},z). \end{align*} $$
    Suppose next that $\Pi (\bar {w},z)$ is $\Pi '(\bar {w},z),(\forall {x})\varphi (x)$ and
    $$ \begin{align*} d'\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}(\bar{w},y),\Pi'(\bar{w},z),\varphi(u){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\mathrm{\Delta}(\bar{w},z), \end{align*} $$
    where ${\mathrm {md}}(d')={\mathrm {md}}(d)$ and x is the only variable occurring in $\varphi $ . Since y occurs in $\mathrm {\Gamma }$ and z occurs in $\Pi ,\mathrm {\Delta }$ , it follows from side-condition (i) for $({\forall \,{\Rightarrow }})$ that $u\in \bar {w}\cup \{y,z\}$ . The case of $u\in \bar {w}\cup \{z\}$ is very similar to the first subcase above, so consider $u=y$ . An application of the induction hypothesis produces $\chi '(\bar {w})\in \mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1+}(\mathcal {L}_s)$ and derivations $d_1',d_2'$ such that and
    $$ \begin{align*} d_1'\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}(\bar{w},y),\varphi(y){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\chi'(\bar{w}),\quad d_2'\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\Pi'(\bar{w},z),\chi'(\bar{w}){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\mathrm{\Delta}(\bar{w},z). \end{align*} $$
    Let . Extending $d_1'$ with applications of $({\forall \,{\Rightarrow }})$ and $({\Rightarrow }\to )$ yields a derivation $d_1$ such that and
    $$ \begin{align*} d_1\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}(\bar{w},y){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\chi(\bar{w}). \end{align*} $$
    Also, $d_2'$ and an instance $(\forall {x})\varphi (x){{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}(\forall {x})\varphi (x)$ of combined with an application of $(\to {\Rightarrow })$ yield a derivation $d_2$ such that and
    $$ \begin{align*} d_2\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\Pi'(\bar{w},z),(\forall{x})\varphi(x),\chi(\bar{w}){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\mathrm{\Delta}(\bar{w},z). \end{align*} $$
  • $({\Rightarrow }\,\forall )$ : Suppose that $\mathrm {\Delta }(\bar {w},z)$ is $(\forall {x})\varphi (x)$ and for some variable u that does not occur freely in $\mathrm {\Gamma }(\bar {w},y),\Pi (\bar {w},z){{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}(\forall {x})\varphi (x)$ ,

    $$ \begin{align*} d'\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}(\bar{w},y),\Pi(\bar{w},z){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\varphi(u), \end{align*} $$
    where ${\mathrm {md}}(d')={\mathrm {md}}(d)-1$ and x is the only variable occurring in $\varphi $ . An application of the induction hypothesis produces $\chi '(\bar {w},u)\in \mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1+}(\mathcal {L}_s)$ and derivations $d^{\prime }_{1},d^{\prime }_{2}$ such that and
    $$ \begin{align*} d_1'\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}(\bar{w},y){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\chi'(\bar{w},u),\quad d^{\prime}_2\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\Pi(\bar{w},z),\chi'(\bar{w},u){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\varphi(u). \end{align*} $$
    Let . Extending $d_1'$ with an application of $({\Rightarrow }\,\forall )$ yields a derivation $d_1$ such that and
    $$ \begin{align*} d_1\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}(\bar{w},y){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\chi(\bar{w}). \end{align*} $$
    Also, extending $d_2'$ with applications of $({\forall \,{\Rightarrow }})$ and $({\Rightarrow }\,\forall )$ yield a derivation $d_2$ such that and
    $$ \begin{align*} d_2\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\Pi(\bar{w},z),\chi(\bar{w}){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}(\forall{x})\varphi(x). \end{align*} $$
  • $({\Rightarrow }\,\exists )$ : Suppose that $\mathrm {\Delta }(\bar {w},z)$ is $(\exists {x})\varphi (x)$ and

    $$ \begin{align*} d'\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}(\bar{w},y),\Pi(\bar{w},z){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\varphi(u), \end{align*} $$
    where ${\mathrm {md}}(d')={\mathrm {md}}(d)$ and x is the only variable occurring in $\varphi $ . Since y occurs in $\mathrm {\Gamma }$ and z occurs in $\Pi ,\mathrm {\Delta }$ , it follows from side-condition (i) for $({\Rightarrow }\,\exists )$ that $u\in \bar {w}\cup \{y,z\}$ . For the first subcase, suppose that $u\in \bar {w}\cup \{z\}$ . An application of the induction hypothesis produces $\chi (\bar {w})\in \mathrm { Fm}_{\forall }^{1+}(\mathcal {L}_s)$ and derivations $d_1,d_2'$ such that and
    $$ \begin{align*} d_1\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}(\bar{w},y){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\chi(\bar{w}),\quad d_2'\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\Pi(\bar{w},z),\chi(\bar{w}){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\varphi(u). \end{align*} $$
    If u occurs in $\Pi (\bar {w},z),\chi (\bar {w})$ , then extending $d_2'$ with an application of $({\Rightarrow }\,\exists )$ yields a derivation $d_2$ such that and
    $$ \begin{align*} d_2\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\Pi(\bar{w},z),\chi(\bar{w}){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}(\exists{x})\varphi(x). \end{align*} $$
    Otherwise, by substituting u uniformly with z in $d_2'$ , we obtain a derivation of $\Pi (\bar {w},z),\chi (\bar {w}){{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}\varphi (z)$ and obtain $d_2$ as described previously.

    For the second subcase, consider $u=y$ . An application of the induction hypothesis produces $\chi '(\bar {w})\in \mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1+}(\mathcal {L}_s)$ and derivations $d_1',d_2'$ such that and

    $$ \begin{align*} d_1'\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\Pi(\bar{w},z){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\chi'(\bar{w}),\quad d_2'\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}(\bar{w},y),\chi'(\bar{w}){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\varphi(y). \end{align*} $$
    Let . Combining $d_2'$ with applications of $({\Rightarrow }\,\exists )$ and $({\Rightarrow }\to )$ yields a derivation $d_1$ such that and
    $$ \begin{align*} d_1\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}(\bar{w},y){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\chi(\bar{w}). \end{align*} $$
    Also, combining the instance $(\exists {x})\varphi (x){{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}(\exists {x})\varphi (x)$ of and $d_1'$ with $(\to {\Rightarrow })$ yields a derivation $d_2$ such that and
    $$ \begin{align*} d_2\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\Pi(\bar{w},z),\chi(\bar{w}){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}(\exists{x})\varphi(x). \end{align*} $$
  • $(\exists \,{\Rightarrow })$ : Suppose first that $\mathrm {\Gamma }(\bar {w},y)$ is $\mathrm {\Gamma }'(\bar {w},y),(\exists {x})\varphi (x)$ and for some variable u that does not occur freely in $\mathrm {\Gamma }(\bar {w},y),\Pi (\bar {w},z){{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}\mathrm {\Delta }(\bar {w},z)$ ,

    $$ \begin{align*} d'\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}'(\bar{w},y),\varphi(u),\Pi(\bar{w},z){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\mathrm{\Delta}(\bar{w},z), \end{align*} $$
    where ${\mathrm {md}}(d')={\mathrm {md}}(d)-1$ and x is the only variable occurring in $\varphi $ . An application of the induction hypothesis produces $\chi '(\bar {w},u)\in \mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1+}(\mathcal {L}_s)$ and derivations $d_1',d_2'$ such that and
    $$ \begin{align*} d_1'\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}'(\bar{w},y),\varphi(u){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\chi'(\bar{w},u),\quad \!d_2'\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\Pi(\bar{w},z),\chi'(\bar{w},u){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\mathrm{\Delta}(\bar{w},z). \end{align*} $$
    Let . Combining $d^{\prime }_1$ with applications of $({\Rightarrow }\,\exists )$ and $(\exists \,{\Rightarrow })$ yields a derivation $d_1$ such that and
    $$ \begin{align*} d_1\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}'(\bar{w},y),(\exists{x})\varphi(x){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\chi(\bar{w}). \end{align*} $$
    Also, extending $d_2'$ with an application of $(\exists \,{\Rightarrow })$ yields a derivation $d_2$ such that and
    $$ \begin{align*} d_2\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\Pi(\bar{w},z),\chi(\bar{w}){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\mathrm{\Delta}(\bar{w},z). \end{align*} $$
    Now suppose that $\Pi (\bar {w},z)$ is $\Pi '(\bar {w},z),(\exists {x})\varphi (x)$ and for some variable u that does not occur freely in $\mathrm {\Gamma }(\bar {w},y),\Pi (\bar {w},z){{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}\mathrm {\Delta }(\bar {w},z)$ ,
    $$ \begin{align*} d'\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}(\bar{w},y),\Pi'(\bar{w},z),\varphi(u){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\mathrm{\Delta}(\bar{w},z), \end{align*} $$
    where ${\mathrm {md}}(d')={\mathrm {md}}(d)-1$ and x is the only variable occurring in $\varphi $ . An application of the induction hypothesis produces $\chi '(\bar {w},u)\in \mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1+}(\mathcal {L}_s)$ and derivations $d_1',d_2'$ such that and
    $$ \begin{align*} d_1'\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}(\bar{w},y){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\chi'(\bar{w},u),\quad d_2'\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\Pi'(\bar{w},z),\varphi(u),\chi'(\bar{w},u){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\mathrm{\Delta}(\bar{w},z). \end{align*} $$
    Let . The derivation $d_1'$ together with an application of $({\Rightarrow }\,\forall )$ yields a derivation $d_1$ such that and
    $$ \begin{align*} d_1\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}(\bar{w},y){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\chi(\bar{w}). \end{align*} $$
    Also, $d_2'$ together with applications of $({\forall \,{\Rightarrow }})$ and $(\exists \,{\Rightarrow })$ yields a derivation $d_2$ such that and
    $$ \begin{align*}d_2\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\Pi(\bar{w},y),(\exists{x})\varphi(x),\chi(\bar{w}){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\mathrm{\Delta}(\bar{w},z).\\[-42pt]\end{align*} $$

Using this lemma we can now reprove, by proof-theoretic means, the special case of Corollary 4.2 for the variety $\mathsf {FL_e}$ .

Theorem 5.3. For any set $T\cup \{\varphi \approx \psi \}$ of $\mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1}(\mathcal {L}_s)$ -equations,

Proof The right-to-left direction follows directly from Corollary 3.8. For the converse, note first that due to compactness and the local deduction theorem for $\vDash ^{\forall }_{\mathsf {V}}$ (see [Reference Cintula and Noguera11, Sections 4.6 and 4.8]), we can restrict to the case where $T = \emptyset $ . Hence, by Proposition 5.1, it suffices to prove that for any sequent $\mathrm {\Gamma }{{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}\mathrm {\Delta }$ consisting only of formulas from $\mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1}(\mathcal {L}_s)$ ,

We proceed by induction on the lexicographically ordered pair , where ${\mathrm {ht}}(d)$ is the height of the derivation d. The base cases are clear and the cases for the last application of a rule in d except $({\Rightarrow }\,\forall )$ and $(\exists \,{\Rightarrow })$ all follow by applying the induction hypothesis and the equations defining $\mathsf {mFL_e}$ . Just note that for each such application, the premises contain only formulas from $\mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1}(\mathcal {L}_s)$ with at least one fewer symbol. In particular, for $({\forall \,{\Rightarrow }})$ and $({\Rightarrow }\,\exists )$ , it can be assumed that the variable u occurring in the premise is x and the result follows using (L1 $_\Box $ ) or (L1 $_\Diamond $ ).

Suppose now that the last rule applied in d is $({\Rightarrow }\,\forall )$ , where $\mathrm {\Delta }$ is $(\forall {x})\psi (x)$ and x may occur freely in $\mathrm {\Gamma }$ . Then $d'\vdash _{_{\mathrm {\forall 1FL_e}}}\mathrm {\Gamma }{{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}\psi (z)$ with ${\mathrm {md}}(d')={\mathrm {md}}(d)-1$ , where z is a variable distinct from x. We write $\mathrm {\Gamma }(y)$ and $d'(y)$ to denote $\mathrm {\Gamma }$ and $d'$ with all free occurrences of x replaced by y. Clearly, $d'(y)\vdash _{_{\mathrm {\forall 1FL_e}}}\mathrm {\Gamma }(y){{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}\psi (z)$ with ${\mathrm {md}}(d'(y))={\mathrm {md}}(d')$ . Note also that no occurrence of y or z lies in the scope of a quantifier in $\mathrm {\Gamma }(y){{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}\psi (z)$ . Hence, by Lemma 5.2, there exist a sentence $\chi $ and derivations $d_1,d_2$ such that and

$$ \begin{align*} d_1\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}(y){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\chi,\quad d_2\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\chi{{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\psi(z). \end{align*} $$

Since $\chi $ is a sentence and x does not occur freely in $\mathrm {\Gamma }(y)$ or $\psi (z)$ , we can assume that $d_1$ and $d_2$ do not contain any free occurrences of x, and, by substituting all occurrences of y in $d_1$ , and z in $d_2$ , with x, obtain derivations $d^{\prime }_1$ of $\mathrm {\Gamma }{{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}\chi $ and $d^{\prime }_2$ of $\chi {{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}\psi (x)$ with ${\mathrm {md}}(d^{\prime }_1)={\mathrm {md}}(d_1)$ and ${\mathrm {md}}(d^{\prime }_2)={\mathrm {md}}(d_2)$ . Hence, by the induction hypothesis twice, and . Since $((\forall {x})\chi )^\ast =\Box \chi ^\ast $ and $\chi $ is a sentence, $\vDash _{\mathsf {mFL_e}}\chi ^\ast \approx ((\forall {x})\chi )^\ast $ , and hence the equations defining $\mathsf {mFL_e}$ yield also . So .

Suppose finally that the last rule applied in d is $(\exists \,{\Rightarrow })$ , where $\mathrm {\Gamma }$ is $\mathrm {\Gamma }',(\exists {x})\psi (x)$ and x may occur freely in $\mathrm {\Gamma }'$ and $\mathrm {\Delta }$ . Then $d'\vdash _{_{\mathrm {\forall 1FL_e}}}\mathrm {\Gamma }',\psi (y){{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}\mathrm {\Delta }$ with ${\mathrm {md}}(d')={\mathrm {md}}(d)-1$ , where y is a variable distinct from x. We write $\mathrm {\Gamma }'(z)$ , $\mathrm {\Delta }(z)$ , and $d'(z)$ to denote $\mathrm {\Gamma }'$ , $\mathrm {\Delta }$ , and $d'$ with all free occurrences of x replaced by z. Clearly, $d'(z)\vdash _{_{\mathrm {\forall 1FL_e}}}\mathrm {\Gamma }'(z),\psi (y){{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}\mathrm {\Delta }(z)$ with ${\mathrm {md}}(d'(z))={\mathrm {md}}(d')$ . By Lemma 5.2, there exist a sentence $\chi $ and derivations $d_1,d_2$ such that and

$$ \begin{align*} d_1\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\psi(y){{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\chi, \quad d_2\vdash_{_{\mathrm{\forall1FL_e}}}\mathrm{\Gamma}'(z),\chi{{\vphantom{A}\Rightarrow{\vphantom{A}}}}\mathrm{\Delta}(z). \end{align*} $$

Since $\chi $ is a sentence and x does not occur freely in $\psi (y)$ , $\mathrm {\Gamma }'(z)$ , or $\mathrm {\Delta }(z)$ , we can assume that $d_1$ and $d_2$ do not contain any free occurrences of x, and, by substituting all occurrences of y in $d_1$ , and z in $d_2$ , with x, obtain derivations $d^{\prime }_1$ of $\psi (x){{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}\chi $ and $d^{\prime }_2$ of $\mathrm {\Gamma }',\chi {{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}\mathrm {\Delta }$ with ${\mathrm {md}}(d^{\prime }_1)={\mathrm {md}}(d_1)$ and ${\mathrm {md}}(d^{\prime }_2)={\mathrm {md}}(d_2)$ . Hence, by the induction hypothesis, and . Since $((\exists {x})\chi )^\ast =\Diamond \chi ^\ast $ and $\chi $ is a sentence, $\vDash _{\mathsf {mFL_e}}\chi ^\ast \approx ((\exists {x})\chi )^\ast $ , and hence the equations defining $\mathsf {mFL_e}$ yield also . So .

The proof-theoretic strategy described above extends easily to varieties of $\mathsf {FL_e}$ -algebras axiomatized relative to $\mathsf {FL_e}$ by equations of a certain simple form. Given a variable x, let $x^0:=\mathrm {e}$ and $x^{k+1}:=x\cdot x^k$ , for each $k\in \mathbb {N}$ , and given a multiset $\Pi $ and $k\in \mathbb {N}$ , let $\Pi ^k$ denote the multiset union of k copies of $\Pi $ . Now let S be the set of equations , and define sequent rules

Given any $S'\subseteq S$ , denote by $\mathsf {FL_e}+S'$ the variety of $\mathsf {FL_e}$ -algebras axiomatized relative to $\mathsf {FL_e}$ by the equations in $S'$ , and by ${\mathrm {\forall 1FL_e}}+r(S')$ the sequent calculus ${\mathrm {\forall 1FL_e}}$ extended with the rules $r(\varepsilon )$ for each equation $\varepsilon $ in $S'$ . Then for any sequent $\mathrm {\Gamma }{{\vphantom {A}\Rightarrow {\vphantom {A}}}}\mathrm {\Delta }$ containing formulas from $\mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1}$ (see, e.g., [Reference Komori18, Reference Ono and Komori23]),

Moreover, the additional cases required to adapt the proof of Lemma 5.2 to ${\mathrm {\forall 1FL_e}}+r(S')$ are straightforward, since each application of a rule $r(\varepsilon )$ for $\varepsilon \in S'$ has just one premise. Hence, following the proof of Theorem 5.3 yields the following more general result.

Theorem 5.4. For any $S'\subseteq S$ and set $T\cup \{\varphi \approx \psi \}$ of $\mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1}(\mathcal {L})$ -equations,

In particular, we obtain alternative proof-theoretic proofs of completeness for the axiomatizations of the one-variable fragments of the first-order extensions of $\mathrm {FL_{ew}}$ , $\mathrm {FL_{ec}}$ , and $\mathrm {FL_{ewc}}$ (intuitionistic logic).

6 Concluding remarks

Let us conclude this paper by mentioning some interesting directions for further research. The most general challenge for a class $\mathsf {K}$ of $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices may be stated as follows: provide a (natural) axiomatization of the equational consequence relation $\vDash ^{\forall }_{\mathsf {K}}$ , or, equivalently, in algebraic terms, provide a (natural) axiomatization of the generalized quasivariety generated by the class of all -functional m- $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices where $\mathbf {A}\in \mathsf {K}$ and W is any set. In this paper, we have shown that when $\mathsf {K}$ is a variety of $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices that has the superamalgamation property, the required generalized quasivariety is the variety $\mathsf {mK}$ of m- $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices (Corollary 4.2), axiomatized relative to $\mathsf {K}$ by a set of axioms familiar from modal logic. However, if $\mathsf {K}$ lacks the superamalgamation property or is not a variety, further axioms may be required.

One potential generalization is to consider varieties of $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices that have the weaker super generalized amalgamation property, which corresponds for substructural logics (even those without exchange) to the Craig interpolation property [Reference Galatos, Jipsen, Kowalski and Ono13]. In particular, such a result would yield an axiomatization for the one-variable fragment of the first-order version of the full Lambek Calculus $\mathrm {FL}$ , although we conjecture that completeness would hold only for valid equations and not consequences. Alternatively, such a generalization might be established proof-theoretically for first-order versions of substructural logics like $\mathrm {FL}$ that have a cut-free sequent calculus, by lifting the proof-theoretic strategy presented in Section 5 to sequents based on sequences of formulas.

A further interesting line of inquiry concerns the case where $\mathsf {K}$ consists of the totally ordered members of a variety of $\mathcal {L}$ -lattices, and hence forms a positive universal class. First, let $\mathsf {V}$ be any variety of semilinear $\mathrm {FL_e}$ -algebras: $\mathcal {L}_s$ -lattices that are isomorphic to a subdirect product of totally ordered $\mathrm {FL_e}$ -algebras. It is not hard to show that in this case, $\vDash ^{\forall }_{\mathsf {V}}(\exists {x})\varphi \cdot (\exists {x})\varphi \approx (\exists {x})(\varphi \cdot \varphi )$ . However, if (e.g., if $\mathsf {V}$ is $\mathsf {MV}$ or the variety of all semilinear $\mathrm {FL_e}$ -algebras), then $\not \vDash _{\mathsf {mV}}\Diamond x\cdot \Diamond x \approx \Diamond (x\cdot x)$ , as proved in Example 3.2, so $\mathsf {mV}$ does not correspond to the one-variable fragment of the first-order logic based on $\mathsf {V}$ .

Now let $\mathsf {V_{to}}$ be the class of totally ordered members of $\mathsf {V}$ . Then not only $\vDash ^{\forall }_{\mathsf {V_{to}}}(\exists {x})\varphi \cdot (\exists {x})\varphi \approx (\exists {x})(\varphi \cdot \varphi )$ , but also , where x does not occur in $\psi $ . Although a general approach to obtaining axiomatizations of the one-variable fragments of the first-order logics based on $\mathsf {V}$ and $\mathsf {V_{to}}$ is lacking, success for specific cases indicate a possible way forward. Most notably, the one-variable fragment of first-order Łukasiewicz logic can be defined over the class $\mathsf {MV_{to}}$ of totally ordered MV-algebras and corresponds to the variety of monadic MV-algebras, defined relative to $\mathsf {mMV}$ by $\Diamond x\cdot \Diamond x \approx \Diamond (x\cdot x)$ and [Reference Rutledge26]. Interestingly, a proof of this latter result is given in [Reference Castaño, Cimadamore, Varela and Rueda8] using the fact that $\mathsf {MV_{to}}$ has the amalgamation property (see also [Reference Metcalfe, Tuyt, Olivetti, Negri, Sandu and Verbrugge21, Reference Tuyt29] for related results), suggesting that the approach developed in this paper might be adapted to one-variable fragments of first-order logics based on classes of totally ordered algebras that have the amalgamation property.

Acknowledgements

The authors would like to thank the anonymous referee for their careful reading of the paper and valuable comments.

Funding

The first author was supported by RVO 67985807 and Czech Science Foundation grant GA22-01137S, and the second two authors by Swiss National Science Foundation grant 200021_215157. This project has also received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme under the Marie Skłodowska-Curie Grant Agreement No. 101007627.

Footnotes

1 A precursor to this paper, reporting preliminary results restricted to a smaller class of logics, was published in the proceedings of AiML 2022 [Reference Cintula, Metcalfe, Tokuda, Fernandéz-Duque, Palmigiano and Pinchinat10].

2 Let us emphasize that an $\mathrm {Fm}_{\forall }^{1}(\mathcal {L})$ -equation $\varphi \approx \psi $ is a primitive syntactic object that relates two formulas and not terms. In some settings (e.g., first-order substructural logics), $\varphi \approx \psi $ can be replaced by a formula such as and semantical consequence can be defined between formulas, but this is not always the case.

3 The full Lambek calculus with exchange is typically presented using sequents consisting of finite sequences of formulas and an “exchange rule” to permute formulas (see, e.g., [Reference Metcalfe, Paoli and Tsinakis20]).

References

Bezhanishvili, G., Varieties of monadic Heyting algebras—part I . Studia Logica , vol. 61 (1998), no. 3, pp. 367402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bezhanishvili, G. and Harding, J., Functional monadic Heyting algebras . Algebra Universalis , vol. 48 (2002), pp. 110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bezhanishvili, G. and Harding, J., MacNeille completions of Heyting algebras . Houston Journal of Mathematics , vol. 30 (2004), pp. 937952.Google Scholar
Bull, R. A., MIPC as formalisation of an intuitionist concept of modality , Journal of Symbolic Logic , vol. 31 (1966), pp. 609616.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caicedo, X., Metcalfe, G., Rodríguez, R., and Rogger, J., Decidability in order-based modal logics . Journal of Computer and System Sciences , vol. 88 (2017), pp. 5374.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caicedo, X., Metcalfe, G., Rodríguez, R., and Tuyt, O., One-variable fragments of intermediate logics over linear frames . Information and Computation , vol. 287 (2022), p. 104755.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caicedo, X. and Rodríguez, R., Bi-modal Gödel logic over -valued Kripke frames . Journal of Logic and Computation , vol. 25 (2015), no. 1, pp. 3755.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Castaño, D., Cimadamore, C., Varela, J. P. D., and Rueda, L., Completeness for monadic fuzzy logics via functional algebras . Fuzzy Sets and Systems , vol. 407 (2021), pp. 161174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ciabattoni, A., Galatos, N., and Terui, K., MacNeille completions of FL-algebras . Algebra Universalis , vol. 66 (2011), no. 4, pp. 405420.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cintula, P., Metcalfe, G., and Tokuda, N., Algebraic semantics for one-variable lattice-valued logics , Proceedings of AiML 2022 (Fernandéz-Duque, D., Palmigiano, A., and Pinchinat, S., editors), Advances in Modal Logic, vol. 14, College Publications, 2022, pp. 237257.Google Scholar
Cintula, P. and Noguera, C., Logic and Implication , Springer, Cham, 2021.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Di Nola, A. and Grigolia, R., On monadic MV-algebras . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 128 (2004), nos. 1–3, pp. 125139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Galatos, N., Jipsen, P., Kowalski, T., and Ono, H., Residuated Lattices: An Algebraic Glimpse at Substructural Logics , Elsevier, Amsterdam, 2007.Google Scholar
Gehrke, M. and Priestley, H. A., Non-canonicity of MV-algebras . Houston Journal of Mathematics , vol. 28 (2002), no. 3, pp. 449456.Google Scholar
Grätzer, G., General Lattice Theory , second ed., Birkhäuser, Basel, 1998.Google Scholar
Halmos, P. R., Algebraic logic, I. Monadic Boolean algebras . Compositio Mathematica , vol. 12 (1955), pp. 217249.Google Scholar
Harding, J., A regular completion for the variety generated by the three-element Heyting algebra . Houston Journal of Mathematics , vol. 34 (2008), no. 3, pp. 649660.Google Scholar
Komori, Y., Predicate logics without the structural rules . Studia Logica , vol. 45 (1986), no. 4, pp. 393404.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maksimova, L. L., Modal logics and varieties of modal algebras: The Beth properties, interpolation, and amalgamation . Algebra i Logika , vol. 31 (1992), no. 2, pp. 145166.Google Scholar
Metcalfe, G., Paoli, F., and Tsinakis, C., Residuated Structures in Algebra and Logic , Mathematical Surveys and Monographs, vol. 277, American Mathematical Society, Providence, 2023.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Metcalfe, G. and Tuyt, O., A monadic logic of ordered abelian groups. Proceedings of AiML 2020 (Olivetti, N., Negri, S., Sandu, G., and Verbrugge, R., editors), Advances in Modal Logic, vol. 13, College Publications, 2020, pp. 441457.Google Scholar
Monteiro, A. and Varsavsky, O., Algebras de Heyting monádicas , Actas de las X Jornadas, Unión Matemática Argentina, Instituto de Matemáticas, Universidad Nacional del Sur, Bahía Blanca , (1957), pp. 5262.Google Scholar
Ono, H. and Komori, Y., Logic without the contraction rule . Journal of Symbolic Logic , vol. 50 (1985), pp. 169201.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ono, H. and Suzuki, N.-Y., Relations between intuitionistic modal logics and intermediate predicate logics . Reports on Mathematical Logic , vol. 22 (1988), pp. 6587.Google Scholar
Rautenberg, W., Modal tableau calculi and interpolation . Journal of Philosophical Logic , vol. 12 (1983), no. 4, pp. 403423.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rutledge, J. D., A preliminary investigation of the infinitely many-valued predicate calculus , Ph.D. thesis, Cornell University, Ithaca, 1959.Google Scholar
Suzuki, N.-Y., An algebraic approach to intuitionistic modal logics in connection with intermediate predicate logics . Studia Logica , vol. 48 (1989), pp. 141155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Suzuki, N.-Y., Kripke bundles for intermediate predicate logics and Kripke frames for intuitionistic modal logics . Studia Logica , vol. 49 (1990), no. 3, pp. 289306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tuyt, O., One-variable fragments of first-order many-valued logics , Ph.D. thesis, University of Bern, 2021.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1 The sequent calculus ${\mathrm {\forall 1FL_e}}$.