Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-swr86 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-16T23:55:56.606Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

4 - Economic Rights in the Knowledge Economy: An Instrumental Justification

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 December 2009

Shareen Hertel
Affiliation:
University of Connecticut
Lanse Minkler
Affiliation:
University of Connecticut
Albino Barrera
Affiliation:
Professor of Economics and Humanities, Providence College
Get access

Summary

JUSTIFYING ECONOMIC RIGHTS

This chapter argues that if one supports efficiency in the knowledge economy, one would also have to support economic rights. There is no consensus among scholars, philosophers, and policy makers on the justification, content, and strength of human rights. Even more intractable is the issue of whether or not economic rights exist at all. Trimiew (1997, 103–68) summarizes three strands of arguments against economic rights. First are the contentions that see an irreconcilable incompatibility between civil-political rights and economic rights. Economic rights give rise to positive obligations that may in fact infringe on the civil-political rights of others. After all, the satisfaction of economic rights entails rival consumption, because they require interpersonal transfers of real resources across economic agents. The second set of objections view the claims of economic rights as incomprehensible. For example, Cranston (1967) argues against economic rights because (a) they are culturally conditioned and therefore not truly universal, (b) they are not always of paramount ultimate value (as in the case of the oft-cited right to a paid vacation [article 24, UN Universal Declaration of Human Rights]), and (c) they are not practicable (as in the case of the right to full and gainful employment for all peoples). Finally, there are those who argue that economic rights only serve to worsen the condition they are meant to ameliorate because they may breed dependency and free-ridership.

Economic rights have been justified on the basis of both their intrinsic worth and their instrumental utility.

Type
Chapter
Information
Economic Rights
Conceptual, Measurement, and Policy Issues
, pp. 76 - 93
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2007

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Arora, Ashish, Fosfuri, Andrea, and Gambardella, Alfonso. 2002. Markets for Technology: The Economics of Innovation and Corporate Strategy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Becker, Gary. 1965. A Theory of the Allocation of Time. Economic Journal 75: 493–515.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blair, Tony. 2005. Speech to the European Parliament, June 23, 2005. http://www.fco.gov.uk/ Files/kfile/UKEUPresidency2005_Sp_PM_EuropeanParliament_230605,0.pdf.
Cohendet, Patrick, and Joly, Pierre-Benoit. 2001. The Production of Technological Know- ledge: New Issues in a Learning Economy. In The Globalizing Learning Economy, ed. Archibugi, Danielle and Lundval, Bengt-Ake. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cowan, Robin, David, Paul, and Foray, Dominique. 2000. The Explicit Economics of Knowledge Codification and Tacitness. Industrial and Corporate Change, 9 (2): 211–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cranston, Maurice. 1967. Human Rights, Real and Supposed. In Political Theory and the Rights of Man, ed. Raphael, D. D.. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Dollar, David, and Kraay, Awart. 2001. Trade, Growth, and Poverty. World Bank Globalization Policy Research Working Paper No. 2615. Washington DC: World Bank.Google Scholar
Dosi, Giovanni, Pavitt, Keith, and Soete, Luc. 1990. The Economics of Technical Change and International Trade. New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Gewirth, Alan. 1982. Human Rights: Essays on Justification and Application. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
John, XXIII. 1963. Pacem in Terris. Boston: Daughters of St. Paul.Google Scholar
Johnson, Bjorn, Lorenz, Edward, and Lundvall, Bengt-Åke. 2002. Why All This Fuss about Codified and Tacit Knowledge? Industrial and Corporate Change 11 (2): 245–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kirzner, Israel. 1997. Entrepreneurial Discovery and the Competitive Market Process: An Austrian Approach. Journal of Economic Literature 35: 60–85.Google Scholar
Kuttner, Robert. 1997. Everything for Sale: The Virtues and Limits of Markets. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.Google Scholar
Lam, Alice. 2000. Tacit Knowledge, Organizational Learning and Societal Institutions: An Integrated Framework. Organization Studies 21 (3): 487–513.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lancaster, Kelvin. 1966. A New Approach to Consumer Theory. Journal of Political Economy 74: 132–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lundvall, Bengt-Åke. 1998. The Learning Economy: Challenges to Economic Theory and Policy. In Institutions and Economic Change: New Perspectives on Markets, Firms and Technology, ed. Nielsen, Klaus and Johnson, Bjorn. Cheltenham, UK, and Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar.Google Scholar
Lundvall, Bengt-Åke. 2001. Innovation Policy in the Globalizing Learning Economy. In The Globalizing Learning Economy, ed. Archibugi, Danielle and Lundvall, Bengt-Åke. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lundval, Bengt-Åke, and Archibugi, Daniele. 2001. Introduction: Europe and the Learning Economy. In The Globalizing Learning Economy, ed. Archibugi, Danielle and Lundvall, Bengt-Åke. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pontifical Council for Peace and Justice. 2004. Compendium of the Social Doctrine of the Church. Vatican City: Libreria Editrice Vaticana.
Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph. 1982. Liberalism, Autonomy, and the Politics of Neutral Concern. In Social and Political Philosophy, ed. French, Peter, Uehling, Theodore Jr. and Wettstein, Howard. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Roberts, Joanne. 2000. From Know-how to Show-how? Questioning the Role of Information and Communication Technologies in Knowledge Transfer. Technology Analysis and Strategic Management 12: 429–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robbins, Lionel. 1932/1952. An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Schultz, Theodore W. 1975. The Value of the Ability to Deal with Disequilibria. Journal of Economic Literature 13: 827–46.Google Scholar
Schultz, Walter. 2001. The Moral Conditions of Economic Efficiency. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schumpeter, Joseph. 1942. Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy. New York: Harper.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1984. Rights and Capabilities. In Resources, Values and Development. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Shapiro, Carl, and Varian, Hal. 1999. Information Rules: A Strategic Guide to the Network Economy. Boston: Harvard Business School Press.Google Scholar
Shue, Henry. 1980. Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence, and U.S. Foreign Policy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Simon, Herbert. 1976. From Substantive to Procedural Rationality. In Method and Appraisal in Economics, ed. Latsis, S.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Solow, Robert. 1987. We'd Better Watch Out (Book Review). New York Times, July 12.Google Scholar
Trimiew, Darryl. 1997. God Bless the Child That Got Its Own: The Economic Rights Debate. Atlanta, GA: Scholars Press.Google Scholar
Triplett, Jack. 1999. The Solow Productivity Paradox: What Do Computers Do to Productivity? Canadian Journal of Economics 32: 309–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hippel, Eric. 1994. “Sticky Information” and the Locus of Problem Solving: Implica- tions for Innovation. Management Science 40: 429–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yergin, Daniel, and Stanislaw, Joseph, 1998. The Commanding Heights: The Battle Between Government and the Marketplace That is Remaking the Modern World. New York: Simon and Schuster.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×