Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-m42fx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-23T02:34:31.386Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

4 - Continuity and meaning: Peirce's pragmatic maxim

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 April 2011

Paul Forster
Affiliation:
University of Ottawa
Get access

Summary

So far I have explained why Peirce thinks nominalists cannot give an adequate account of the meaning of general concepts. The reason is that general concepts define continua and nominalism cannot explain continuity. However, I also noted that the nominalist can concede Peirce's argument and still deny that general concepts represent features of the world. He can argue that if Peirce is right that knowledge of individuals can never add up to knowledge of a continuum, then because experience is the only source of knowledge and individuals are the only objects known through experience, the hypothesis of real continuity is unverifiable and we should at least be agnostic about it, if not reject it outright. Moreover, since no collection of individuals is truly continuous, then, the nominalist will urge, the concept of continuity has no application in the actual world. Thus, positing real continua as objects represented by general concepts violates Ockham's razor.

This defence of nominalism hinges on the contention that the testable content of theories is limited to claims about individuals. Should the nominalist defend this view by appeal either to the metaphysical doctrine that only individuals exist or the psychological doctrine that individuals are the only objects of experience, Peirce will remain unimpressed. As he sees it, the conditions of theory testing are to be investigated in the science of inquiry, and questions in the science of inquiry – questions about the testable content of theories included – must be settled independently of facts about the actual world.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×